[Published by the Office for Protection from Research Risks (now the Office of Human Research Protections), 1993]


 

Institutional Review Board Guidebook

* CHAPTER V I*

SPECIAL CLASSES OF SUBJECTS


 

 

 

Introduction

A.   Fetuses and Human In Vitro Fertilization

Introduction

Definitions

Overview

IRB Considerations

Points to Consider

Applicable Laws

 

B.   Women

Introduction

Definitions

IRB Considerations

Points to Consider

Applicable Laws

 

C.   Children and Minors

Introduction

Definitions

IRB Considerations

Points to Consider

Applicable Laws         

 

D.  Cognitively Impaired Persons

Introduction

Definitions

IRB Considerations

Points to Consider

Applicable Laws

 

       

E.  Prisoners

Introduction

Definitions

IRB Considerations

Points to Consider

Applicable Laws

 

 

F.  Traumatized and Comatose Patients

Introduction

Overview

IRB Considerations

Points to Consider

Applicable Laws

                         

G.   Terminally Ill Patients

Introduction

Overview

IRB Considerations

Points to Consider

Applicable Laws

 

H.  Elderly/Aged Persons

Introduction

IRB Considerations

Points to Consider

Applicable Laws         

            

I.   Minorities

Introduction

IRB Considerations

Points to Consider

Applicable Laws

 

J.   Students, Employees, and Normal Volunteers

Introduction

IRB Considerations

Applicable Laws

 

K.   International Research

Introduction

IRB Considerations

Applicable Laws

                                        

                                                                      
Suggestions for Further Reading


INTRODUCTION

The federal regulations require that IRBs give special consideration to protecting the welfare of particularly vulnerable subjects, such as children, prisoners, pregnant women, mentally disabled persons, or economically or educationally disadvantaged persons [Federal Policy §___.111]. For research to which the DHHS regulations are applicable, the DHHS regulations set forth specific provisions on research involving fetuses, pregnant women, and human in vitro fertilization [45 CFR 46 Subpart B]; prisoners [45 CFR 46 Subpart C]; and children [45 CFR 46 Subpart D]. In general, these special regulations allow IRBs to approve research that is of minimal risk or that will benefit the subjects directly. Investigations involving these subjects that present significantly greater than minimal risk without direct benefit to them must be reviewed and approved by the Secretary of Health and Human Services, in consultation with appropriate experts.

Special Note Regarding Applicability of DHHS Regulations. Institutions with DHHS-approved Assurances on file must abide by the provisions of 45 CFR 46 Subparts A-D. Some of the other departments and agencies have incorporated all provisions of 45 CFR 46 into their policies and procedures as well. The exemptions at 45 CFR 46.101(b), however, do not apply to research involving prisoners, fetuses, pregnant women, or human in vitro fertilization (i.e., research to which Subparts B and C apply). Also, the exemption at 45 CFR 46.101(b)(2), for research involving survey or interview procedures, or observation of public behavior, does not apply to research involving children (i.e., research to which Subpart D applies), except for research involving observations of public behavior when the investigator(s) do not participate in the activities being observed. [See Federal Policy §___.101, footnote 1.]

Return to Top of Page

A. FETUSES AND HUMAN IN VITRO FERTILIZATION

INTRODUCTION

Research involving the human fetus raises special concerns for IRB reviewers. The fetus has a unique and inextricable relationship to the mother. It cannot consent to be a research subject. These circumstances have aroused lengthy public debate on the ethics of fetal research, and led to special federal regulations that guide IRB deliberations about fetal research [45 CFR 46 Subpart B]. The fetus may also be an indirect subject of research when women who may be pregnant participate. Research involving pregnant women is also regulated by 45 CFR 46 Subpart B. [See Guidebook Chapter 6, Section B, “Women.”]

DEFINITIONS

Dead Fetus: An expelled or delivered fetus that exhibits no heartbeat, spontaneous respiratory activity, spontaneous movement of voluntary muscles, or pulsation of the umbilical cord (if still attached) [45 CFR 46.203(f)]. Generally, some organs, tissues, and cells (referred to collectively as fetal tissue) remain alive for varying periods of time after the total organism is dead.

Fetal Material: The placenta, amniotic fluid, fetal membranes, and the umbilical cord.

Fetus: The product of conception from the time of implantation until delivery. If the delivered or expelled fetus is viable, it is designated an infant [45 CFR 46.203(c)]. (Hereafter, the term “fetus” will refer to a living fetus unless otherwise specified.) The term “fetus” generally refers to later phases of development; the term “embryo” is usually used for earlier phases of development.

Human In Vitro Fertilization: Any fertilization involving human sperm and ova that occurs outside the human body.

Minimal Risk: A risk is minimal where the probability and magnitude of harm or discomfort anticipated in the proposed research are not greater, in and of themselves, than those ordinarily encountered in daily life or during the performance of routine physical or psychological examinations or tests [Federal Policy §___.102(i)]. For example, the risk of drawing a small amount of blood from a healthy individual for research purposes is no greater than the risk of doing so as part of routine physical examination.

Nonviable Fetus: An expelled or delivered fetus which, although it is living, cannot possibly survive to the point of sustaining life independently, even with the support of available medical therapy. Although it may be presumed that an expelled or delivered fetus is nonviable at a gestational age less than 20 weeks and weight less than 500 grams [Federal Register 40 (August 8, 1975): 33552], a specific determination as to viability must be made by a physician in each instance.

Pregnancy: The period from confirmation of implantation of a fertilized egg within the uterus until the fetus has entirely left the uterus (i.e., has been delivered). Implantation is confirmed through a presumptive sign of pregnancy such as missed menses or a positive pregnancy test [45 CFR 46.203(b)]. This “confirmation” may be in error, but, for research purposes, investigators would presume that a living fetus was present until evidence to the contrary was clear. Although fertilization occurs a week or more before implantation, the current inability to detect the fertilization event or the presence of a newly fertilized egg makes a definition of pregnancy based on implantation necessary.

Viable Infant: When referring to a delivered or expelled fetus, the term “viable infant” means likely to survive to the point of sustaining life independently, given the benefit of available medical therapy. This judgment is made by a physician. In accordance with DHHS regulations, the Secretary, HHS, may publish guidelines to assist in the determination of viability. Such guidelines were published in 1975, and specify an estimated gestational age of 20 weeks or more and a body weight of 500 grams or more as indices of fetal viability [Federal Register 40 (August 8, 1975): 33552]. These indices depend on the state of present technology and may be revised periodically.

OVERVIEW

In the early 1970s, considerable national concern was expressed about the ethics of fetal research and about reports of ethically questionable procedures involving human fetuses. Partly in response to these concerns, Congress established the National Commission for the Protection of Human Subjects in 1974, required that it study the subject of fetal research and make recommendations concerning such research to the Department of Health, Education and Welfare (the precursor of DHHS), and imposed a moratorium on federally funded fetal research until regulations based upon the Commission’s recommendations were in place. Subsequent DHHS regulations on this subject implemented fully the recommendations of the National Commission. Congress may, from time to time, impose further limitations on research involving the human fetus; similarly, a number of states have laws affecting such research.

Although the Commission did not define the “personhood” of the fetus, it recognized the genetic heritage and vulnerability of the fetus, and affirmed that it should be treated respectfully and with dignity, regardless of its life prospects. The Commission also affirmed the legitimacy and importance of fetal research for improving the health of fetuses both in the present and the future. Risks to the fetus from any research procedure must not be more than minimal (e.g., from ultrasound or changes in maternal diet). If the risks exceed the level considered minimal, they must be justified by anticipated benefit for the health of the mother or the particular fetus.

The concept of minimal risk is evaluative rather than objective; considerable room for interpretation exists. In an effort to impart some objectivity, regulations concerning competent adult subjects define minimal risk in terms of those risks encountered in everyday life or in routine physical or psychological examinations [Federal Policy §___.102(i)]. Determinations of minimal risk to a fetus, however, can challenge an IRB. If risk to the fetus is deemed to be more than minimal and without anticipated medical benefit to the mother or the fetus, special provisions apply.

IRB CONSIDERATIONS

In addition to the general requirements for review of research by the IRB, prior research with animal subjects, and, if feasible, research with nonpregnant persons should form the basis of the risk/benefit assessment for fetal research. The proposed research should seek information not obtainable in any other way. If abortion is involved, the investigators may have no part in either the decision to abort or decisions about the timing or the method to be used; no change in the abortion procedure that would present more than minimal risk to the fetus or its mother can be introduced for research purposes. No monetary or other inducements (e.g., free care) may be offered to a woman to induce her to terminate her pregnancy for research purposes.

Ethics Advisory Board. The DHHS regulations mandate the establishment of a national Ethics Advisory Board whose responsibility is to render advice to the Secretary on various issues. Applications involving human in vitro fertilization must be reviewed by the Ethics Advisory Board before they can be funded [45 CFR 46.204]. Similarly, requests for modification or waiver of the regulatory requirements (e.g., research involving greater than minimal risk where therapeutic benefit to the fetus is lacking) must be approved by the Board. If the Board approves the request, the Secretary may authorize support of the research if the knowledge to be gained can be obtained in no other way and is important enough to justify the risk involved [45 CFR 46.211].

The Board’s charter, however, expired in 1980 and has not been renewed as of this writing. Applications for federally-sponsored research involving human in vitro fertilization and embryo transfer may therefore not be funded until a Board is reestablished. Research protocols that require a waiver or modification of the regulatory requirements are similarly restricted. The Guidebook will provide updated information on the status of an Ethics Advisory Board as information becomes available.

Research Directed Toward the Fetus In Utero. Research in which the welfare of a fetus in utero must be considered may involve the fetus either directly or indirectly. The research may be directed toward the pregnant woman (in which case the fetus is indirectly involved), the fetus (in which case it is directly involved) or both. Where it is directed toward both the pregnant woman and the fetus in utero, the regulations pertaining to both subjects apply [45 CFR 46.207 (activities directed toward pregnant women as subjects) and 45 CFR 46.208 (activities directed toward fetuses in utero as subjects)]. Research directed toward the pregnant woman is discussed in Guidebook Chapter 6, Section B, “Women.

An IRB may approve research directed toward the fetus in utero if: (1) the purpose of the research is to meet the health needs of the fetus and is conducted in a way that will minimize risk (e.g., a new technique for fetal transfusion for Rh incompatibility); or (2) the research poses no more than minimal risk to the fetus (e.g., minor changes in maternal diet or use of ultrasonography) and the purpose of the activity is the development of important biomedical knowledge that is unobtainable by other means [45 CFR 46.208]. Many possibilities for intrauterine treatment of fetuses are presently being explored. The initial efforts in this field will inevitably be innovative and experimental. When proposals for research on fetal therapy come before an IRB, the risks should be justified by a reasonable possibility of benefitting the fetus (e.g., increased chance of survival or avoidance of severe disability).

Research Involving the Fetus Ex Utero. If an ex utero fetus is judged viable (i.e., likely to survive to the point of sustaining life independently, given the benefit of available medical therapy), it is then called an infant. At this point, an IRB must be guided by regulations and policies dealing with children. [See 45 CFR 46 Subpart D.] A fetus is judged nonviable if it cannot possibly survive to the point of sustaining life independently, even with the support of available medical therapy, and will therefore die. Research involving a nonviable fetus that would either artificially maintain vital functions or hasten their failure is forbidden. Ethical considerations call upon investigators to maintain the dignity of this dying human subject and to avoid unseemly intrusions in the process of dying for research purposes [45 CFR 46.209].

Research With Dead Fetuses, Fetal Material, and the Placenta. Research activities involving the dead fetus, macerated fetal material, or cells, tissue, or organs excised from a dead fetus are governed by state laws and regulations [45 CFR 46.210]. The National Commission recommended that, in addition to conforming to such laws, research involving dead fetuses be compatible with commonly held views about respect for the dead.

Fetal Tissue Transplantation Research. Research involving the use of human fetal tissue obtained from induced abortions into patients suffering from such disorders as Parkinson Disease and juvenile diabetes has been the subject of considerable debate in the biomedical community. A moratorium on federally-funded research involving the therapeutic transplantation into humans of fetal tissue obtained from induced abortions, which was imposed by the Assistant Secretary for Health in 1988, was lifted on January 22, 1993, by presidential memorandum [Federal Register 58:7457 (February 5, 1993)]. A panel convened by NIH to deliberate on the concerns that gave rise to the moratorium issued recommendations regarding the ethical use of fetal tissue from induced abortions in therapeutic transplantation research [U.S. Department of Health and Human Services. Public Health Service. National Institutes of Health (1988b)]. The panel’s report was approved by NIH in December 1988. NIH has issued interim guidelines for the support and conduct of therapeutic human fetal tissue transplantation research [NIH Guide for Grants and Contracts 22 (No. 11, March 19, 1993)]. The interim guidelines, which closely follow the panel’s recommendations, provide as follows:

Separating Abortion from Research

  • The decision to terminate a pregnancy and procedures of abortion should be kept independent from the retrieval and use of fetal tissue.
  • The timing and method of abortion should not be influenced by the potential uses of fetal tissue for transplantation or medical research.

Prohibiting Payments and Other Inducements

  • Payments and other forms of remuneration and compensation associated with the procurement of fetal tissue should be prohibited, except payment for reasonable expenses occasioned by the actual retrieval, storage, preparation, and transportation of the tissues.

Informed Consent

  • Potential recipients of such tissues, as well as research and health care participants, should be properly informed about the source of the tissues in question.
  • The decision and consent to abort must precede discussion of the possible use of the fetal tissue and any request for such consent that might be required for that use.
  • Fetal tissue from induced abortions should not be used in medical research without the prior consent of the pregnant woman. Her decision to donate fetal remains is sufficient for the use of tissue, unless the father objects (except in cases of incest or rape).
  • Consent should be obtained in compliance with state law and with the Uniform Anatomical Gift Act.

Prohibiting Directed Donations

  • The pregnant woman should be prohibited from designating the transplant recipient of the fetal tissue.
  • Anonymity between donor and recipient should be maintained, so that the donor does not know who will receive the tissue, and the identity of the donor is concealed from the recipient and transplant team.
  • Experimental transplants performed with fetal tissue from induced abortions provided by a family member, friend, or acquaintance should be prohibited.

Abiding by State and Local Laws

  • Researchers in states with statutes appearing to ban fetal tissue transplants should seek clarification of the law.

Ethical Review of Research

  • Customary review procedures should apply to research involving transplantation of tissue from induced abortions.

Determining When Progress to Clinical Studies is Justified

  • Sufficient evidence from animal experimentation is needed to justify proceeding to human clinical trials. Acceptable preliminary data must be presented to an appropriate Institutional Review Board, NIH Initial Review Group, and National Advisory Council before Public Health Service funds would be available.

Resources discussing the ethical issues involved in the use of human fetal tissue for transplantation are provided in the “Suggestions for Further Reading” section at the end of this chapter. Restrictions on the use of fetal material for research purposes is an evolving area of the law. In addition to any federal requirements concerning the use of fetal tissue in research, many states have adopted legislation governing the use of fetal tissue, including use for transplantation purposes. IRBs should be aware of and adhere to any legal requirements relevant to their review of protocols that include the use of fetal tissue.

Research in Anticipation of Abortion. There are conflicting views about whether research in anticipation of abortion is permissible. Some people believe such research exploits already difficult (some consider the situation morally unacceptable) circumstances; others feel that the opportunity to test drugs or procedures on fetuses whose mothers have already made a decision to abort poses little real risk to those fetuses, while the research may save other fetuses from considerable risk. For example, some drugs produce birth defects if taken during pregnancy because they pass through the placenta to the fetus, and tests performed on animals - even primates - are not always a reliable indicator of what will happen in humans. To evaluate this effect accurately, experimental drugs must be tested in women to see whether they cross the placenta. It has been suggested that such tests pose less risk to a fetus-to-be-aborted than to a fetus going to term, because there is not time for the harm (e.g., birth defect) to materialize prior to abortion. There are, however, two ethical problems in this situation. First, the woman may change her mind about having the abortion after taking the experimental drug. Second, regardless of life prospects, the fetus is an unconsenting subject.

The National Commission for the Protection of Human Subjects wrestled with this problem and concluded that there is no difference between the moral status of a fetus destined for abortion and that of a fetus to be carried to term. Therefore, only those research procedures that would be acceptable for a fetus going to term may be performed in anticipation of abortion. If the IRB determines that the risk is acceptable for fetuses that will be carried to term, it is acceptable to select only fetuses-to-be-aborted as subjects. By limiting the risk to what is acceptable for the fetus to be carried to term, the right of the mother to change her mind about abortion is protected; by selecting only those fetuses destined for abortion as subjects, risk to fetuses carried to term is minimized. In practical terms, research procedures that take place at the same time and during the same process as the abortion itself most fully meet these conditions (e.g., a fetoscopic procedure initiated after administering drugs to initiate abortion).

Consent for Research Involving Fetuses. In all research in which human fetuses are the subjects of research, the consent of the mother on behalf of the fetus is required. As a general rule, the consent of the father on behalf of the fetus is also required before a fetus may be enrolled in research. Exceptions to the requirement that the father provide consent are permitted if: (1) the father’s identity or whereabouts cannot reasonably be ascertained; (2) the father is not reasonably available; or (3) the pregnancy resulted from rape [45 CFR 46.107(b) and 45 CFR 46.208(b)].

The drafters of the regulations reasoned that the father’s consent should be obtained in cases where the father is known and reasonably available for several reasons: (1) as co-progenitor, the father has an interest second only to that of the mother in the well-being of the fetus; (2) the father will be held legally responsible for the health needs of the child, and since these health needs may be affected by participation in research, the father ought to have a voice in determining to what risks the fetus should be exposed; and (3) involvement of a fetus in research in cases where the parents are not in agreement concerning participation is likely to disrupt the family unit as a whole, an additional risk for the fetus.

The IRB should provide guidance to investigators to assist in determining when a father is “reasonably available.” Some examples of situations in which a father is customarily judged not to be “reasonably available” will assist the IRB in providing direction to investigators:

  • Paternity is uncertain. In such cases it is not necessary for the IRB or the research investigator to attempt to establish paternity.
  • The father’s whereabouts cannot be readily ascertained.
  • The father does not acknowledge that he is the father of the fetus.
  • The father has assumed no responsibility for the pregnancy and has manifested no interest in or has denied responsibility for the well-being of the fetus. [Note: It may be sufficient for an investigator to obtain a statement to this effect from the mother. No further assessment of the facts is required].

Investigators should document their reasons for deciding that a father was not “reasonably available” and should feel free to consult with the IRB in cases where applicability of the requirement for paternal consent is not clear.

In all studies, IRBs should ensure that the information provided to the parent(s) clearly distinguishes procedures performed for research purposes from procedures performed as a part of the standard care of medicine. Risks to the mother should be, so far as possible, distinguished from risks to the fetus; the limits of knowledge about the extent of those risks should be clearly presented.

Waiver of Specific Requirements by the Secretary. The Secretary, HHS, may modify or waive specific conditions or requirements of the regulations governing fetal research on the advice of a national Ethics Advisory Board and after an opportunity for public comment [45 CFR 46.211]. The primary considerations are whether the risks to the subject are so outweighed by the sum of the benefit to the subject and the importance of the knowledge to be gained as to warrant the modification or waiver, and whether the benefits of the research can be gained only if the modification or waiver is granted. [See discussion of the Ethics Advisory Board, above.]

The only waiver granted to date was in 1979 for research designed to assess the risk of fetoscopy as a method of prenatal diagnosis of genetic disorders. (It involved inserting a hollow tube into the uterus and extracting a small blood sample from the fetus for examination and testing.) Subjects were to be women who had already decided to undergo an abortion. Since the risk of the procedure was undetermined, it could not be said to be minimal; moreover, no medical benefit to the women or their fetuses was contemplated. Thus, the Department could not support the research without a waiver by the Secretary; that, in turn, required review and approval of the Ethics Advisory Board. The Board’s report on this matter, with its conclusion that the research was ethically acceptable, was published in the Federal Register for public comment [Federal Register 44 (August 14, 1979): 47732]. The Secretary subsequently granted the waiver and provided support for the research.

Additional Restrictions on Fetal Research. Congress imposes additional restrictions on fetal research from time to time; IRBs should therefore consult with OPRR if they are unsure of the current status of such research.

Research Involving Human In Vitro Fertilization. DHHS regulations require all research involving human in vitro fertilization or embryo transfer to be reviewed by a national Ethics Advisory Board before it can be funded by the Department [45 CFR 46.204(d)]. The lapse in the Board has precluded federal funding of human in vitro fertilization research. The American College of Obstetricians and Gynecologists (ACOG) and the American Fertility Society (AFS) have recently established a National Advisory Board on Ethics in Reproduction, which plans to establish guidelines for research in this area. IRBs reviewing privately funded in vitro fertilization research might consider consulting with the new ACOG/AFS advisory board.

Levine (1986) provides an overview of the issues presented by in vitro fertilization, as well as resources for further reading. He notes that while the Ethics Advisory Board found research on in vitro fertilization ethically acceptable and set forth criteria for conducting such research [see Report (June 18, 1979)], the Board did not foresee many of the issues that have since been identified. One issue of importance to IRBs is what Levine calls “the problem of ‘spare’ embryos” [pp. 315-319]. IRBs should assure that investigators have clearly addressed what will happen to embryos that are not used in the particular embryo transfer procedure for which they were created (e.g., “they [will] be used for research purposes, they [will] be implanted in the uterus of another woman, or they [will] be destroyed”); investigators should ensure that participants are informed of and consent, in writing, to the resolution of this question. Investigators should also clarify to participants the ownership of the embryos that are not used in the procedure (e.g., that they “belong” to the laboratory and may not be removed by the parents, or that they “belong” to the biological mother). Levine describes how these questions were reviewed by the IRB at the Yale University School of Medicine [pp. 317-319].

POINTS TO CONSIDER

1. Is animal research an appropriate prerequisite? Has it been completed? Where appropriate and feasible, has research with nonpregnant women been completed?

2. If there is any risk to a fetus, is the information sought judged to be important? Could it be obtained by any other means?

3. Is risk to the fetus minimal?

4. In research with a nonviable fetus ex utero, is any intervention proposed that would shorten or prolong the natural course of dying?

5. Are the investigators involved in any decisions about an abortion process (e.g., timing or method) that is related to the research?

6. Is abortion encouraged for research purposes (e.g., are free care or services offered)?

7. Do any applicable federal, state, or local laws restrict such research?

8. From whom must consent be obtained?

APPLICABLE LAWS AND REGULATIONS

45 CFR 46 Subpart B

[DHHS: Additional protections pertaining to research, development, and related activities involving fetuses, pregnant women, and in vitro fertilization]

Federal Register 58:7457 (February 5, 1993)

[Fetal tissue transplantation research]

NIH Guide for Grants and Contracts 22

(No. 11, March 19, 1993) [NIH interim guidelines for the support and conduct of therapeutic human fetal tissue transplantation research]

Federal, state, and local laws governing research involving human fetuses or fetal material

Return to Top of Page

B. WOMEN

INTRODUCTION

Special regulatory requirements govern the participation of pregnant women in research [45 CFR 46 Subpart B]. Research involving women who are or may become pregnant receives special attention from IRBs because of women’s additional health concerns during pregnancy and because of the need to avoid unnecessary risk to the fetus. Further, in the case of a pregnant woman, IRBs must determine when the informed consent of the father to the research is required. Special attention is justified because of the involvement of a third party (the fetus) who may be affected but cannot give consent and because of the need to prevent harm or injury to future members of society. Procedural protections beyond the basic requirements for protecting human subjects are prescribed in DHHS regulations for research involving pregnant women [45 CFR 46 Subpart B]. No specific DHHS regulations are directed toward research involving lactating women.

The inclusion of women in research studies is discussed in this Section and in Guidebook Chapter 3, Section C, “Selection of Subjects.”


DEFINITIONS

Lactation: The period of time during which a woman is providing her breast milk to an infant or child.

Minimal Risk: A risk is minimal where the probability and magnitude of harm or discomfort anticipated in the proposed research are not greater, in and of themselves, than those ordinarily encountered in daily life or during the performance of routine physical or psychological examinations or tests [Federal Policy §___.102(i)]. For example, the risk of drawing a small amount of blood from a healthy individual for research purposes is no greater than the risk of doing so as part of routine physical examination.

Pregnancy: The period from confirmation of implantation of a fertilized egg within the uterus until the fetus has entirely left the uterus (i.e., has been delivered). Implantation is confirmed through a presumptive sign of pregnancy such as missed menses or a positive pregnancy test [45 CFR 46.203(b)]. This “confirmation” may be in error, but, for research purposes, investigators would presume that a living fetus was present until evidence to the contrary was clear. Although fertilization occurs a week or more before implantation, the current inability to detect the fertilization event or the presence of a newly fertilized egg makes a definition of pregnancy based on implantation necessary.

IRB CONSIDERATIONS

Pregnant women may be involved in several categories of research. IRB duties differ in each category, but the primary objectives are assessing: (1) whether the research is directed toward the mother’s health or toward the fetus; and (2) the risks to the woman and to the fetus or infant. Subsequent actions depend on those assessments. Research directed toward the fetus is discussed in Guidebook Chapter 6, Section A, “Fetuses and Human In Vitro Fertilization.” For research activities directed toward pregnant women as subjects, the federal regulations provide that no pregnant woman may be involved as a subject unless either: (1) the purpose of the activity is to meet the health needs of the mother, and the fetus will be placed at risk only to the minimum extent necessary to meet such needs; or (2) the risk to the fetus is minimal [45 CFR 46.207].

Inclusion of Women in Study Populations. NIH policy requires the inclusion of women and minorities in research study populations so that research findings can be of benefit to all persons at risk of the disease, disorder, or condition under study. Specifically, the NIH policy states:

Applications for grants and cooperative agreements that involve human subjects are required to include minorities and both genders in study populations so that research findings can be of benefit to all persons at risk of the disease, disorder or condition under study; special emphasis should be placed on the need for inclusion of minorities and women in studies of diseases, disorders and conditions which disproportionately affect them. This policy applies to all research involving human subjects and human materials, and applies to males and females of all ages. If one gender and/or minorities are excluded or are inadequately represented in this research, particularly in proposed population-based studies, a clear compelling rationale for exclusion or inadequate representation should be provided. The composition of the proposed study population must be described in terms of gender and racial/ethnic group, together with a rationale for its choice. In addition, gender and racial/ethnic issues should be addressed in developing a research design and sample size appropriate for the scientific objectives of the study.

Assess carefully the feasibility of including the broadest possible representation of minority groups. However, NIH...recognize[s] that it may not be feasible or appropriate in all research projects to include representation of the full array of United States racial/ethnic minority populations (i.e., American Indians or Alaskan Natives, Asians or Pacific Islanders, Blacks, Hispanics). Provide the rationale for studies on single minority population groups.

Applications for support of research involving human subjects must employ a study design with gender and/or minority representation (by age distribution, risk factors, incidence/prevalence, etc.) appropriate to the scientific objectives of the research. It is not an automatic requirement for the study design to provide statistical power to answer the questions posed for men and women and racial/ethnic groups separately; however, whenever there are scientific reasons to anticipate differences between men and women, and racial/ethnic groups, with regard to the hypothesis under investigation, applicants should include an evaluation of these gender and minority group differences in the proposed study. If adequate inclusion of one gender and/or minorities is impossible or inappropriate with respect to the purpose of the research because of the health of the subjects, or other reasons, or if in the only study population available, there is a disproportionate representation of one gender or minority/majority group, the rationale for the study population must be well explained and justified [PHS Grant Application form 398, pp. 21-22].

[See also publication and interpretation of the NIH policy in the NIH Guide for Grants and Contracts 20 (No. 32, August 23, 1991): 1-3.]

In addition, principal investigators of funded grants and cooperative agreements falling under the scope of the policy must report annually on the number of subjects planned and enrolled to date by ethnic origin and gender [Application for Continuation of a Public Health Service Grant, form 2590, pp. 7-9 and Form Page 7].

This information should also be available for IRB review, both for its initial review and for its annual review for continuation of projects. The role of the IRB in assuming responsibility for reviewing the adequacy of representation of women and minorities in studies has been controversial. IRBs around the country have deliberated the relevance of the inclusion of women and minorities in studies to their consideration of whether the welfare and safety of subjects are adequately protected. Their responses cross the entire spectrum of possibilities, from considering the question irrelevant to regarding it as one of utmost importance. Discussion is continuing at many levels in the federal government in an effort to develop IRB guidance policies. NIH expects to provide further guidance concerning the policy, which will be published in the NIH Guide for Grants and Contracts during 1993.

Discussion centers on issues of justice, beneficence, appropriate levels of inclusion, generalizability of study results, and liability of sponsors. The exclusion of women from studies raises considerations of justice because exclusion deprives women from the possibility of directly benefitting from participation (e.g., receiving a potentially beneficial medical therapy).

Exclusion or inappropriate representation further raises issues of generalizability: If women are excluded or are not appropriately represented, the data generated by the study may not be generalizable beyond the male study population; women as a class will therefore not benefit. In considering the inclusion of women in the study, IRBs should note the limitations on generalizability that may result from study size or other factors. The ability to evaluate gender differences may depend on sample sizes that the investigator cannot reasonably attain.

Women of child-bearing potential may be excluded from studies not only because of concern for the welfare of the fetus, but also because of possible legal liability of sponsors and investigators for harm caused by investigational agents or other research activities. Consideration of the liability issue requires balancing the protection of women and potential fetuses against the benefits that would result from their inclusion (i.e., direct benefits and the generalizability of data).

Until a consensus is reached on this question, IRBs should continue to consider representation of women in study protocols in their deliberations on the adequacy of protections of the safety and welfare of subjects.

In 1977 the FDA issued guidelines limiting the involvement of women of childbearing potential in Phase 1 and early Phase 2 clinical drug trials, with which IRBs should be familiar. [See General Considerations for the Clinical Evaluation of Drugs (1977) and Guidelines for the Format and Content of the Clinical and Statistical Sections of New Drug Applications (1988).] The FDA is reevaluating its policy on the exclusion of women of childbearing potential from such clinical studies [U.S. General Accounting Office (1992)], and has indicated that it will revise the 1977 guidelines to permit and encourage the inclusion of women of childbearing potential in research.

Studies in Which Pregnancy is Coincidental to Subject Selection. Any study in which women of childbearing potential are possible subjects may inadvertently include pregnant women. DHHS regulations require that, when appropriate, subjects be provided a “statement that the particular treatment or procedure may involve risks to the subject (or to the embryo or fetus, if the subject is or may become pregnant) which are currently unforeseeable” as part of the informed consent process [Federal Policy §___.116(b)(1)]. IRBs must judge whether the mother’s participation would pose any risk to the fetus or nursing infant. In some studies, IRBs may need to ensure that nonpregnant subjects are advised to avoid pregnancy or nursing for a time during or following the research. Furthermore, where appropriate, subjects should be advised to notify the investigator immediately should they become pregnant. In some instances there may be potential risk sufficient to justify requiring that pregnant women either be specifically excluded from the research or studied separately.

Studies Directed Primarily Toward the Mother’s Health. Many women enter pregnancy with health problems or develop new ones during pregnancy. Some problems are affected positively or negatively by pregnancy; others are unaffected. A considerable amount of research is conducted on health problems that occur during pregnancy (e.g., arthritis, hypertension, diabetes); despite standard therapy, deterioration of maternal health may also necessitate experimental treatment. In research undertaken to meet the health problems of a pregnant woman, her needs generally take precedence over those of the fetus [45 CFR 46.207], except, perhaps, where the health benefit to the woman is minimal and risk to the fetus is high. If, for example, an experimental drug were considered necessary to improve a pregnant woman’s condition, her consent alone would be sufficient to authorize its administration - even though it might have unknown or greater than minimal risk for the fetus. In reviewing such studies IRBs must attempt to ensure that the risk to the fetus is minimized, consistent with achieving the research objective.

Studies Directed Toward Pregnancy. Numerous studies are conducted that address the normal and abnormal processes of pregnancy, labor, and delivery. Some (e.g., studying the physiological mechanisms maintaining pregnancy or initiating labor) are not directed to the health of either the mother or fetus. Others (e.g., studying the effects of strict control of maternal diabetes on pregnancy outcome) involve research on improving maternal health and research on the fetus, thus requiring review for both sets of considerations. [See Guidebook Chapter 6, Section A, “Fetuses and Human In Vitro Fertilization.”] The requirements for IRB approval will sometimes conflict, depending on how the research is categorized (e.g., whether or not it is directed toward improving maternal health determines the degree of fetal risk permitted and paternal consent requirements). In such instances, the IRB will have to determine which circumstances prevail and which requirements apply.

The primary requirement for approval in this category is an IRB determination that the risk to the fetus is “minimal.” The broad definition of minimal risk places great responsibility for good judgment on IRB members. The definition suggests that if the estimated risk to the fetus is no more than that from established procedures routinely used in an uncomplicated pregnancy or in a pregnancy with complications comparable to those being studied, the risk is considered minimal. Ultrasound exams, maternal exercise comparable to job- or recreation-related levels, amniocentesis, and delivery in a sitting position might be considered minimally risky in most pregnancies. If the IRB cannot conclude that fetal risk is minimal, it may conditionally approve the research, subject to review and approval by the Secretary, HHS [45 CFR 46.211]. As with fetal research, the Secretary may modify or waive specific conditions or requirements of the regulations governing fetal research on the advice of a national Ethics Advisory Board and after an opportunity for public comment [45 CFR 46.211]. The primary consideration is whether the risks to the subjects are so outweighed by the sum of the benefit to the subjects and the importance of the knowledge to be gained as to warrant the modification or waiver. A further consideration is whether the benefits of the research can be gained without the modification or waiver.

Consent. Once the research is approved under the IRB’s minimal risk standard, the IRB must make a judgment regarding the consent. DHHS regulations require both the woman’s and the father’s consent for research in this category unless: (1) the purpose of the research is to meet the health needs of the mother; (2) the father’s identity or whereabouts cannot reasonably be ascertained; (3) he is not reasonably available; or (4) the pregnancy resulted from rape. Issues of consent are discussed in Chapter 6, Section A, “Fetuses and Human In Vitro Fertilization.”

Lactating Women. Although there are no specific regulations for research involving lactating women, IRB review should include a focus on safety for the nursing infant (the mother’s own child or one to whom she provides her milk). IRBs should require that investigators provide assurance that taking breast milk samples, maternal dietary modifications, drugs given to the mother, or other research manipulations will not unduly threaten the supply or nutritional content of colostrum or milk for nursing infants.

Studies to Develop or Evaluate Methods of Enhancing Conception or Contraception. These studies are closely related to research involving pregnant women and raise some of the same concerns. There are no special regulations for this category of research, but special IRB attention is needed. IRBs should ensure that there is an adequate explanation of the risks, benefits, reversibility, and alternatives; that backup protection against unintended pregnancy is provided when appropriate; and that the possibility of failure (and options available for dealing with unintended pregnancies) are satisfactorily described.

Research on Abortion Techniques. DHHS regulations do not deal directly with research on abortion techniques. In reviewing such research, risks to the woman would be a primary consideration. IRBs should keep in mind, however, that if a fetus survived the abortion and was viable, the infant might be severely damaged. IRBs must be aware of local requirements and the most current federal laws and policies before proceeding to review the proposed research.

Exemption from Review. Note that the exemptions from IRB review provided for in 45 CFR 46.101(b) [Federal Policy §___.101(b)] do not apply to research involving pregnant women [Federal Register 56 (June 18, 1991): 28013, note 1].

POINTS TO CONSIDER

1. For all studies, is there reason to exclude pregnant or lactating women? If so, how strict should the screening measures be?

2. For all studies involving pregnant women, have appropriate studies on animals and nonpregnant humans been conducted? Is any special monitoring of the informed consent process needed?

3. For studies directed toward maternal health, is the risk to the fetus the least possible consistent with the research objectives? Will the mother be adequately informed of the potential risk to the fetus and of alternative treatments and their risks and benefits?

4. For studies of pregnancy, labor, or delivery, is the risk to the fetus “minimal?” Is the father’s consent required?

5. For studies of lactating women, is the supply and content of breast milk adequately protected?

6. For studies of conception or contraception, are the risks, benefits, reversibility, and alternatives adequately explained? In contraceptive studies, is there adequate explanation of possible failure and of the options available for dealing with unintended pregnancies?

7. Will women be appropriately represented in the study? Does the study need to be designed to allow evaluation of gender differences?

APPLICABLE LAWS AND REGULATIONS

Federal policy for the protection of human subjects

21 CFR 50.25(b)(1)

[FDA: Informed consent]

45 CFR 46, Subpart B

[DHHS: Additional protections pertaining to research, development, and related activities involving fetuses, pregnant women, and in vitro fertilization]

Applicable regulations of the Department of Agriculture, the Army, and the Air Force

Federal laws that may limit research involving the living human fetus

State and local laws governing research involving human fetuses

NIH policy concerning inclusion of women and minorities in study populations. NIH Guide for Grants and Contracts 20 (No. 32, August 23, 1991): 1-3. The policy also appears in the application packet for PHS Grants, form PHS 398, pp. 21-22, and in NIH Requests for Proposals (RFPs).

Application for Continuation of a Public Health Service Grant, form 2590, pp. 7-9 and Form Page 7.

U.S. Department of Health and Human Services. Public Health Service. Food and Drug Administration. General Considerations for the Clinical Evaluation of Drugs. Washington, D.C.: U.S. Government Printing Office, 1977. (Under revision.)

U.S. Department of Health and Human Services. Public Health Service. Food and Drug Administration. Guidelines for the Format and Content of the Clinical and Statistical Sections of New Drug Applications. Washington, D.C.: U.S. Government Printing Office, 1988.

Return to Top of Page

C. CHILDREN AND MINORS

INTRODUCTION

The ethical mandate of IRBs is to protect the rights and welfare of human research subjects. IRBs are obligated to ensure that research studies do not endanger the safety or well-being of human subjects or undermine public confidence in the conduct of research. The special vulnerability of children makes consideration of involving them as research subjects particularly important. To safeguard their interests and to protect them from harm, special ethical and regulatory considerations are in place for reviewing research involving children. Title 45 CFR Part 46, Subpart D provides for “Additional Protections for Children Involved as Subjects of Research.” Research that is contrary to the rights and welfare of child-subjects is prohibited. A good summary of the ethical considerations surrounding research involving children can be found in Levine (1989).

DEFINITIONS

Assent: A child’s affirmative agreement to participate in research. Mere failure to object should not be construed as assent [45 CFR 46.402(b)].

Benefit: A valued or desired outcome; an advantage.

Children: Persons who have not attained the legal age for consent to treatment or procedures involved in the research, as determined under the applicable law of the jurisdiction in which the research will be conducted [45 CFR 46.402(a)].

Emancipated Minor: A legal status conferred upon persons who have not yet attained the age of legal competency as defined by state law, but who are entitled to treatment as if they had by virtue of assuming adult responsibilities, such as self-support, marriage or procreation. (See also: Mature Minor.)

Guardian: An individual who is authorized under applicable state or local law to give permission on behalf of a child to general medical care [45 CFR 46.402(e) ].

Mature Minor: Someone who has not reached adulthood (as defined by state law) but who may be treated as an adult for certain purposes (e.g., consenting to medical care). Note that a mature minor is not necessarily an emancipated minor. (See also: Emancipated Minor.)

Minimal Risk: A risk is minimal where the probability and magnitude of harm or discomfort anticipated in the proposed research are not greater, in and of themselves, than those ordinarily encountered in daily life or during the performance of routine physical or psychological examinations or tests [Federal Policy §___.102(i)]. For example, the risk of drawing a small amount of blood from a healthy individual for research purposes is no greater than the risk of doing so as part of routine physical examination.

Permission: The agreement of parent(s) or guardian to the participation of their child or ward in research [45 CFR 46.402(c)].

Risk: The probability of harm or injury (physical, psychological, social, or economic) occurring as a result of participation in a research study. Both the probability and magnitude of possible harm may vary from minimal to significant. Federal regulations define only “minimal risk.” (See also: Minimal Risk.)

IRB CONSIDERATIONS

Analysis of Probable Risks, Possible Benefits, and Associated Discomforts. IRBs reviewing research involving children as subjects must consider the benefits, risks, and discomforts inherent in the proposed research and assess their justification in light of the expected benefits to the child-subject or to society as a whole. In calculating the degree of risk and benefit, the IRB should weigh the circumstances of the subjects under study, the magnitude of risks that may accrue from the research procedures, and the potential benefits the research may provide to the subjects or class of subjects.

The federal regulations require IRBs to classify research involving children into one of four categories and to document their discussions of the risks and benefits of the research study. The four categories of research involving children that may be approved by IRBs, based on degree of risk and benefit to individual subjects, are as follows:

1. Research not involving greater than minimal risk [45 CFR 46.404].

2. Research involving greater than minimal risk, but presenting the prospect of direct benefit to an individual subject. Research in this category is approvable provided: (a) the risk is justified by the anticipated benefit to the subject; and (b) the relationship of risk to benefit is at least as favorable as any available alternative approach [45 CFR 46.405].

3. Research involving greater than minimal risk with no prospect of direct benefit to individual subjects, but likely to yield generalizable knowledge about the subject’s disorder or condition. Research in this category is approvable provided: (a) the risk represents a minor increase over minimal risk; (b) the intervention or procedure presents experiences to subjects that are reasonably commensurate with those inherent in their actual or expected medical, dental, psychological, social, or educational settings; and (c) the intervention or procedure is likely to yield generalizable knowledge about the subject’s disorder or condition that is of vital importance for the understanding or amelioration of the subject’s disorder or condition [45 CFR 46.406].

4. Research that is not otherwise approvable, but which presents an opportunity to understand, prevent, or alleviate a serious problem affecting the health or welfare of children. Research that is not approvable under 45 CFR 46.404, 46.405, or 46.406 may be conducted or funded by DHHS provided that the IRB, and the Secretary, after consultation with a panel of experts, finds that the research presents a reasonable opportunity to further the understanding, prevention, or alleviation of a significant problem affecting the health and welfare of children. The panel of experts must also find that the research will be conducted in accordance with sound ethical principles [45 CFR 46.407].

In all cases, the IRB must determine that adequate provisions have been made for soliciting the assent of children and the permission of their parents or guardians [45 CFR 46.408].

Assessing Probable Risks. Central to IRBs’ consideration of research involving children is the determination of what constitutes minimal risk. Procedures that usually present no more than minimal risk to a healthy child include: urinalyses, obtaining small blood samples, EEGs, allergy scratch tests, minor changes in diet or daily routine, and/or the use of standard psychological or educational tests. The assessment of the probability and magnitude of the risk, however, may be different in sick children and may vary depending on the diseases or conditions the subjects may have. For example, obtaining blood samples from a hemophiliac child may present more than minimal risk to the child. On the other hand, IRBs may consider that children suffering from chronic illnesses who are accustomed to invasive procedures are placed at minimal risk by involvement in similar research procedures, in contrast to children who have not had such experiences. The IRB must also consider the extent to which research procedures would be a burden to any child, regardless of whether the child is accustomed to the proposed procedures.

Procedures that exceed the limits of minimal risk may be difficult to define in the abstract, but should not be too difficult to identify on a case-by-case basis. Riskier procedures might include biopsy of internal organs, spinal taps, or the use of drugs whose risks to children have not yet been established. Behavioral interventions likely to cause psychological stress may also exceed minimal risk.

Assessing Possible Benefits. In assessing the possible benefits of research intervention, the IRB should consider the variability in health statuses among potential subjects. For example, a potential subject might be a normal, healthy child, or a child who has been exposed to a disease or a toxin (e.g., meningococcus or lead) where it is known that a percentage of the children exposed will actually experience untoward consequences. A child may also be in an early state of disease, e.g., an HIV-infected child, or may actually suffer from disease or other significant medical condition. Thus the IRB must take into account the current health status of a child and the likelihood of progression to a worsened state without research intervention.

Phase 1 Trials. The issue of Phase 1 drug studies deserves special consideration. The usual approach to designing drug studies involving children as subjects is for appropriate studies to be conducted first in animals, adults, and older children before young children are involved as research subjects. There are some studies, however, in which data may not be entirely generalizable from older populations, and in which the existence of life-threatening conditions for children are important considerations in the IRB’s risk/benefit analysis. The requirement for previous testing in adults or older children may thus not be appropriate. Furthermore, some diseases specific to children may require that children be involved without data from older groups (e.g., there is no adult model that mimics the state of HIV-infected newborns; Wilms’ tumor and various cancers such as neuroblastoma affect infants who do not survive into older childhood.) In some cases “tandem” studies in older populations and children may be justifiable. For example, some Phase 1 studies in children might be based on only pharmacologic safety and toxicity data (completed Phase 1 and ongoing Phase 2) but without complete effectiveness data from trials in adults and older children. If the IRB approves a Phase 1 drug trial, the consent document must specify what is known about the probability that, and the degree to which, an intervention will be of possible benefit based on all of these data.

Consent Procedures. When children or minors are involved in research, the regulations require the assent of the child or minor and the permission of the parent(s), in place of the consent of the subjects.

Given that children have not reached their full intellectual and emotional capacities and are legally unable to give valid consent, involving children in research requires the permission of their parents or legally authorized representatives. The IRB must determine whether the permission of both parents is necessary, and the conditions under which one parent may be considered “not reasonably available” [45 CFR 46.408]. (Examples of circumstances in which parental permission may be inappropriate are discussed below.) In addition, the regulations require that the IRB determine that adequate provisions are made for soliciting the assent of the children, when in the judgment of the IRB the children are capable of providing assent [45 CFR 46.408(a)].

The regulations provide that an IRB may find that the permission of one parent is sufficient for research to be conducted under 45 CFR 46.404 (minimal risk research) or 45 CFR 46.405 (research involving greater than minimal risk but presenting the prospect of direct benefit to individual subjects) [45 CFR 46.408(b) ]. Where research is covered by 45 CFR 46.406 and 45 CFR 46.407, and permission is to be obtained from parents, both parents must give their permission, unless one parent is deceased, unknown, incompetent, or not reasonably available, or when only one parent has legal responsibility for the care and custody of the child [45 CFR 46.408(b)].

While children may be legally incapable of giving informed consent, they nevertheless may possess the ability to assent to or dissent from participation. Out of respect for children as developing persons, children should be asked whether or not they wish to participate in the research, particularly if the research: (1) does not involve interventions likely to be of benefit to the subjects; and (2) the children can comprehend and appreciate what it means to be a volunteer for the benefit of others. The IRB must determine for each protocol - depending on such factors as the nature of the research and the age, status, and condition of the proposed subjects - whether all or some of the children are capable of assenting to participation. Where appropriate, IRBs may choose to review on a case-by-case basis whether assent should be sought from given individual subjects. The federal regulations do not require that assent be sought from children starting at a specific age, but that their assent should be sought when, in the judgment of the IRB, the children are capable of providing their assent. IRBs are to take into account the ages, maturity, and psychological state of the children involved [45 CFR 46.408(a)].

When the research offers the child the possibility of a direct benefit that is important to the health or well-being of the child and is available only in the context of the research, the IRB may determine that the assent of the child is not necessary [45 CFR 46.408(a)]. Additionally, in such circumstances a child’s dissent, which should normally be respected, may be overruled by the child’s parents, at the IRB’s discretion. When research involves the provision of experimental therapies for life-threatening diseases such as cancer, however, IRBs should be sensitive to the fact that parents may wish to try anything, even when the likelihood of success is marginal and the probability of extreme discomfort is high. Should the child not wish to undertake such experimental therapy, difficult decisions may have to be made. In general, if the child is a mature adolescent and death is imminent, the child’s wishes should be respected.

When the IRB determines that the assent of the child is required, it must also determine that the provisions for obtaining and documenting assent are adequate [45 CFR 46.408(e)]. The child should be given an explanation of the proposed research procedures in a language that is appropriate to the child’s age, experience, maturity, and condition. This explanation should include a discussion of any discomforts and inconveniences the child may experience if he or she agrees to participate.

For some research activities, IRBs may require that either an IRB member or an advocate for the child be present during the assent and permission procedures to verify the child’s understanding and to support the child’s preferences. The IRB may also require that the parent(s) or a close family member be present during the research, especially if a young child will be exposed to significant discomfort or inconvenience, or if the child will be required to spend time in an unfamiliar place.

The requirement for parental permission may be inappropriate in some cases. Examples include research involving older adolescents who, under applicable law, may consent on their own behalf for selected treatments (e.g., treatment for venereal disease, drug abuse, or emotional disorders). In other research (e.g., research on child abuse or neglect), there may be serious doubt as to whether the parents’ interests adequately reflect the child’s interests. In these cases, IRBs should devise alternative procedures for protecting the rights and interests of the children asked to participate, including, perhaps, the court appointment of special guardians.

Parental permission may sometimes be insufficient to protect the child’s interests. In cases involving transplants (e.g., of bone marrow or a kidney) between minor siblings, the parents’ concern for the afflicted child may interfere with their consideration of the best interests of the healthy donor. Therefore, IRBs may want to consider asking for court review of the parents’ decision. [See also Guidebook Chapter 5, Section G, “Transplants.”]

The IRB should consult legal counsel about the applicability of any state laws affecting consent for the proposed research. The IRB should be aware of the age of majority in the state as well as laws or court decisions that might limit the right of parents to consent on behalf of their children in certain circumstances. Age and conditions of emancipation will differ from state to state. In some states the age at which a child can give consent to medical care differs depending on the medical condition involved (e.g., venereal diseases). The federal regulations require that all research activities must comply not only with the regulations but also with the law of the state in which they are performed.

Exemption From Review. The exemption at 45 CFR 46.101(b)(2), for research involving survey or interview procedures or observation of public behavior, does not apply to research with children covered by Subpart D, except for research involving observations of public behavior when the investigator(s) do not participate in the activities being observed. The remaining exemptions in 45 CFR 46.101(b)(2) apply to research involving children.

Wards of the State. The special protections for children set forth in Subpart D include additional limitations on some research involving children who are wards of the state or any other agency, institution, or entity. Where the research involves greater than minimal risk to the subjects with no prospect of direct benefit to individual subjects (45 CFR 46.406), or requires HHS Secretarial approval (45 CFR 46.407), the research must either be related to their status as wards, or else be conducted in schools, camps, hospitals, institutions, or similar settings in which the majority of children involved as subjects are not wards [45 CFR 46.409]. The IRB must require, for each child who is a ward, appointment of an advocate in addition to any other individual acting on behalf of the child as a guardian or in loco parentis.

IRBs should be particularly concerned with the involvement of HIV-infected children who are in foster care, but who are also not wards. Many of these children are from racial or ethnic minorities. IRBs need to give special attention to groups of children such as these who, while they need special protections, should not be denied the opportunity to participate in research that may potentially be of benefit to them.

Finally, whenever institutionalized children might be involved in research, care should be taken to ensure that they are not included as participants simply because of their availability to the investigator.

POINTS TO CONSIDER

1. Does the research have an identifiable prospect of direct benefit to the individual child participant? Can that benefit be achieved through alternative means?

2. Does the research have an identifiable prospect of risk to the individual child participant? What safeguards are proposed to minimize these risks? When procedures involving greater than minimal risk to children are anticipated, are convincing scientific and ethical justifications given?

3. Is the inclusion of normal volunteers justified?

4. Do studies involving placebo controls place the child at greater risk by withholding from selected subjects potentially therapeutic research drugs or interventions?

5. When possible, have appropriate studies been conducted on animals and adults first? Will older children be enrolled before younger ones?

6. What is the age of majority in the state? Can a child consent to medical care for certain conditions, and, if so, at what age? What legal limits are there on the right of parents to consent on behalf of their children?

7. Is permission of both parents necessary? Under what conditions may one of the parents be considered “not reasonably available?”

8. Will efforts be made to ensure that parents’ permission to involve their children in research studies is free from coercion, exploitation, and/or unrealistic promises?

9. Are mechanisms in place to ensure that children are involved as research subjects in ways that do not undermine their dignity as young persons? Are provisions made that show respect for the developing rights of children, such as: (a) obtaining their assent, and, where appropriate, honoring their dissent; and (b) protecting their need for privacy and the confidentiality of information regarding them?

10. Are there special problems that call for the presence of a monitor or advocate during consent procedures?

11. Are special needs of adolescents such as counseling and confidentiality accounted for in the research design?

12. Are there any special problems such as confidentiality and reporting that might arise in sensitive research about child abuse or sexual practices of teenagers?

13. If conditions present in children have implications for other family members’ health statuses, are appropriate mechanisms proposed for dealing with the larger family unit (e.g., genetic risks or HIV infection)?

14. Should parents be required to be present during the conduct of the research? (Are proposed subjects to be very young? Are the procedures involved painful? Must subjects stay overnight in the hospital when they otherwise would not have to?)

APPLICABLE LAWS AND REGULATIONS

45 CFR 46 Subpart D

[DHHS: Additional protections for children involved as subjects in research]

The IRB should consult legal counsel about any applicable state laws affecting research involving children as subjects, including laws affecting consent procedures.

Return to Top of Page

D. COGNITIVELY IMPAIRED PERSONS

INTRODUCTION

The predominant ethical concern in research involving individuals with psychiatric, cognitive, or developmental disorders, or who are substance abusers is that their disorders may compromise their capacity to understand the information presented and their ability to make a reasoned decision about participation. Many individuals with disabilities affecting their reasoning powers may be residents of institutions responsible for their total care and treatment. The impact of institutionalization may further compromise their ability to exercise free choice (voluntariness). (These concerns apply both to voluntary patients and those committed involuntarily.) The eagerness for release may induce an institutionalized person, especially one who is involuntarily confined, to participate in research out of a desire to appear “rational” and “cooperative” to those who will make decisions about his or her release.

It is important to protect the privacy of all subjects and the confidentiality of information gathered in research exploring emotionally sensitive topics. Many patients do not want even the fact of their institutionalization divulged.

DEFINITIONS

Cognitively Impaired: Having either a psychiatric disorder (e.g., psychosis, neurosis, personality or behavior disorders), an organic impairment (e.g., dementia) or a developmental disorder (e.g., mental retardation) that affects cognitive or emotional functions to the extent that capacity for judgment and reasoning is significantly diminished. Others, including persons under the influence of or dependent on drugs or alcohol, those suffering from degenerative diseases affecting the brain, terminally ill patients, and persons with severely disabling physical handicaps, may also be compromised in their ability to make decisions in their best interests.

Competence: Technically, a legal term, used to denote capacity to act on one’s own behalf; the ability to understand information presented, to appreciate the consequences of acting (or not acting) on that information, and to make a choice. (See also: Incompetence, Incapacity.)

Competence may fluctuate as a function of the natural course of a mental illness, response to treatment, effects of medication, general physical health, and other factors. Therefore, mental status should be re-evaluated periodically. As a designation of legal status, competence or incompetence pertains to an adjudication in court proceedings that a person’s abilities are so diminished that his or her decisions or actions (e.g., writing a will) should have no legal effect. Such adjudications are often determined by inability to manage business or monetary affairs and do not necessarily reflect a person’s ability to function in other situations.

Incapacity: Refers to a person’s mental status and means inability to understand information presented, to appreciate the consequences of acting (or not acting) on that information, and to make a choice. Often used as a synonym for incompetence.

Incompetence: Technically, a legal term meaning inability to manage one’s own affairs. Often used as a synonym for incapacity.

Institution: A residential facility that provides food, shelter, and professional services (including treatment, skilled nursing, intermediate or long-term care, and custodial or residential care). Examples include general, mental, or chronic disease hospitals; inpatient community mental health centers; halfway houses and nursing homes; alcohol and drug addiction treatment centers; homes for the aged or dependent, residential schools for the mentally or physically handicapped; and homes for dependent and neglected children.

IRB CONSIDERATIONS

IRBs that regularly review research involving vulnerable subjects (such as the mentally disabled) are required by DHHS and FDA regulations to consider including among their members one or more individuals who are knowledgeable about and experienced in working with those subjects [45 CFR 46.107; 21 CFR 56.107]. In addition, the IRB must be sure that additional safeguards are in place to protect the rights and welfare of these subjects [45 CFR 46.111(b); 21 CFR 56.111(b)]. Unlike research involving children, prisoners and fetuses, however, no additional DHHS regulations specifically govern research involving persons who are cognitively impaired.

The recommendations of the National Commission for the Protection of Human Subjects resemble the recommendations made with respect to children. [See Guidebook Chapter 6, Section C, “Children and Minors.”] More recently, Annas and Glantz (1986) have argued that research should involve cognitively impaired subjects only where: (1) they comprise the only appropriate subject population; (2) the research question focuses on an issue unique to subjects in this population; and (3) the research involves no more than minimal risk. Levenson and Hamric (1989) argue that research involving greater than minimal risk may be acceptable where the purpose of the research is therapeutic with respect to individual subjects and where the risk is commensurate with the degree of expected benefit.

Selection of Subjects. It is now generally accepted that research involving persons whose autonomy is compromised by disability or restraints on their personal freedom should bear some direct relationship to their condition or circumstances. Persons who are institutionalized, particularly if disabled, should not be chosen for studies that bear no relation to their situation just because it would be convenient for the researcher. An institutional setting can be advantageous to the conduct of research - the population is easily accessible, close supervision to prevent extraneous influences is possible, and medical monitoring and emergency services are available. Some not uncommon characteristics of the institutional setting, however, create circumstances that may compromise the voluntary nature of participation in research. For example, institutionalized individuals may have become emotionally dependent on their caretakers and may acquiesce too readily to requests for their “cooperation.” Persons who are totally dependent on an institution may be vulnerable to perceived or actual pressures to conform to institutional wishes for fear of being denied services or privileges. If medical care, staff attention, or living conditions are inadequate, an invitation to move into a special unit or research ward may be appealing. Finally, with little or no opportunity to make decisions regarding their daily living, the ability of institutionalized subjects to make choices may be further diminished.

Nevertheless, IRBs should not make assumptions as to the effect of an institutional setting on voluntariness or competence. People do not automatically become incapable of competent and voluntary consent the moment they enter a mental institution. On the other hand, institutionalized individuals (particularly retarded persons) have been used as convenient research subjects in drug tests totally unrelated to their disorders or institutionalization. This exploitation of the vulnerable and the “voiceless” led the National Commission to recommend that, even in research on mental disabilities, subjects should be recruited from among noninstitutionalized populations whenever possible.

Degree of Risk. No clear consensus exists on the acceptable degree of risk when mentally compromised persons are involved in the research. One position holds that research that presents more than minimal risk should involve mentally compromised persons only if they will derive a direct and significant benefit from participation. The National Commission recommended that a minor increase over minimal risk may be permitted in research involving those institutionalized as mentally disabled, but only where the research is designed to evaluate an intervention of foreseeable benefit to their care. For research that does not involve beneficial interventions and that presents more than minimal risk, the National Commission recommended that the anticipated knowledge sought should be of vital importance for understanding or eventually alleviating the subject’s disorder or condition. Finally, the National Commission recommended that there be additional ethical review at the national level for research projects the IRB believes should be supported - because the knowledge to be gained may be of major significance to the prevention, diagnosis, or treatment of mental disorders - but that would not otherwise be approved at the local level. The American College of Physicians has similarly recommended the creation of a national board to review research that involves more than minimal risk and that carries no direct benefit for the subjects [1989, p. 846]. Since the mechanism of a national board is not currently available, IRBs reviewing such research should consider obtaining assistance from expert consultants.

Limiting Risks. IRBs must be sure that investigators have included a description of appropriate psychological or medical screening criteria to prevent or reduce the chances of adverse reactions to the therapeutic and research procedures. When appropriate, IRBs might want to require that other health care providers be consulted to ensure that proposed research procedures will not be detrimental to ongoing therapeutic regimens. Specific diagnostic, symptomatic, and demographic criteria for subject recruitment should be described in the research proposal.

Any plan to hospitalize subjects or extend hospitalization for research purposes should be justified by the investigator. The effects of separation from supportive family or friends, of disruption in schooling or employment, and the question of responsibility for bearing any additional costs should be carefully considered by the IRB. Methods for assuring adequate protections for the privacy of the subjects and the confidentiality of the information gathered should also be described by the investigator. Individually identifiable information that is “sensitive” should be safeguarded, and requests for the release of such information to others, for research or auditing, should be allowed only when continued confidentiality is guaranteed.

Problems of Consent and Competence. Consent to research involving cognitively impaired subjects through any of the intramural programs of the National Institutes of Health (e.g., the National Institute of Mental Health, the National Institute of Neurological and Communicative Disorders and Stroke, the National Institute on Aging, and the National Institute on Alcohol Abuse and Alcoholism) is guided by NIH policy on consent to research with impaired human subjects. This policy sets out, in matrix form, conditions under which cognitively impaired subjects may participate in research of varying risk.

As a general rule, all adults, regardless of their diagnosis or condition, should be presumed competent to consent unless there is evidence of serious mental disability that would impair reasoning or judgment. Even those who do have a diagnosed mental disorder may be perfectly able to understand the matter of being a research volunteer, and quite capable of consenting to or refusing participation. Mental disability alone should not disqualify a person from consenting to participate in research; rather, there should be specific evidence of individuals’ incapacity to understand and to make a choice before they are deemed unable to consent.

Persons formally adjudged incompetent have a court-appointed guardian who must be consulted and consent on their behalf. Officials of the institution in which incompetent patients reside (even if they are the patient’s legal guardians) are not generally considered appropriate, since their supervisory duties may give rise to conflicting interests and loyalties. Family members or others financially responsible for the patient may also be subject to conflicting interests because of financial pressures, emotional distancing, or other ambivalent feelings common in such circumstances. IRBs should bear this in mind when determining appropriate consent procedures for cognitively impaired subjects.

Some individuals may be incompetent and have no legal guardian. One such example would be mentally retarded adults whose parents “voluntarily” institutionalized them as children and have never subsequently gone through formal proceedings to determine incompetence and have a guardian appointed. Another example would be geriatric patients with progressive cognitive disorders (e.g., senile dementia of the Alzheimer type). Typically, a spouse or adult child of such patients consents to their medical care, but no one is a “legally authorized representative.” The extent to which family members may legally consent to the involvement of such patients in research (especially if no benefit to the subjects is anticipated) is not clear. According to a position paper published by the American College of Physicians (1989), surrogates of cognitively impaired persons should not consent to research that holds out no expected benefit if such research presents more than minimal risk of harm or discomfort. As mentioned earlier, the ACP also, however, recommended the creation of a national board to review research that involves more than minimal risk and that carries no direct benefit for the subjects [1989, p. 846].

Because no generally accepted criteria for determining competence to consent to research (for persons whose mental status is uncertain or fluctuating) exist, the role of the IRB in assessing the criteria proposed by the investigator is of major importance. The selection of an appropriate representative to consent on behalf of those unable to consent for themselves must be accomplished without clear guidance from statutes, case law, or regulations. Within the boundaries of existing legal precedents, IRBs can be creative in helping investigators formulate appropriate procedures in these uncertain areas. IRBs should be sure, however, to seek legal advice to determine the applicability of state laws that might affect the participation of legally incompetent persons in research. [See also Levine (1986), pp. 270-76.]

IRBs should be cautious about recommending legal proceedings to establish guardianship for the purpose of obtaining consent for research participation. Despite a temptation to recommend this course of action to “be on the safe side,” depriving individuals of their freedom should not be taken lightly. Many states give guardians and conservators authority to make nearly all important decisions on behalf of the individual they represent. (These decisions are conditioned by an anticipated benefit to the individual.) The National Commission recommended that guardianships established for purposes of authorizing participation in research be limited to the provision and continuance (or withdrawal) of permission regarding the subject’s participation in the research. The National Commission also urged that, despite the fact that consent may be obtained from a legally authorized representative or guardian, the feelings and expressed wishes of an incompetent person should still be respected. IRBs should consider whether to require investigators to solicit prospective subjects’ “assent” (i.e., the willing and, to the extent possible, knowledgeable participation of those unable to give legally valid consent). IRBs should also determine whether an incompetent person’s refusal to participate in research should override consent given by a legal guardian. The National Commission recommended that such decisions be based on the amount of risk involved in the research and the likelihood that the subjects will derive health benefits from their participation. [See Report and Recommendations: Research Involving Those Institutionalized as Mentally Infirm, Recommendations 2, 3, and 4.] The National Commission also recommended that in the case of research involving more than minimal risk, the objection of an adult subject who is incapable of consenting should be binding, unless the individual’s participation is specifically authorized by a court of law, the intervention is expected to provide a direct health benefit to the subject, and the intervention is available only in the context of the research. [See id., Recommendation 4.] Note, however, that where local law allows institutionalized persons the right to refuse therapy, objections to participation may not be overridden.

Procedures can sometimes be developed to enhance the possibility that subjects can consent for themselves. Criteria for determining competence might vary according to the degree of risk or discomfort presented by the research procedures and the extent to which therapeutic gains can be anticipated. The setting in which consent is sought and the person seeking it can also influence a potential subject’s ability to comprehend or appreciate what is being asked. An uncomfortable chair, a room that is either too noisy or lacking in privacy, or a physician the patient dislikes may all create anxiety or resistance that would not exist if the information were presented by another person, at another time, or in another place. The National Commission recommended that, in certain cases, a consent auditor be appointed by the IRB to determine whether proposed subjects consent, assent, or object to their participation in research, especially if the research involves more than minimal risk and no foreseeable direct benefit.

POINTS TO CONSIDER

1. Does the IRB need to include a member knowledgeable about and experienced with the mentally disabled or cognitively impaired?

2. Does the research pertain to mental disabilities so that it is necessary to involve persons who are mentally disabled as subjects?

3. If the investigator proposes to involve institutionalized individuals, has he or she provided sufficient justification for using that population? Are noninstitutionalized subjects appropriate for the research and reasonably available? Does the research pertain to aspects of institutionalization?

4. Are adequate procedures proposed for evaluating the mental status of prospective subjects to determine whether they are capable of consenting? Are these procedures appropriate both to the subject population and the nature of the proposed research?

5. Is more than minimal risk involved? If so, is the risk justified by anticipated benefits to the participating subjects and the importance of the knowledge that may reasonably be expected to result?

6. Is it possible to identify persons authorized to give legally valid consent on behalf of any individuals judged incapable of consenting on their own behalf? Should assent of the prospective subjects also be required? If incapable of giving valid consent, can subjects’ objection to participation be overridden? Under what circumstances?

7. Should an advocate or consent auditor be appointed to ensure that the preferences of potential subjects are elicited and respected? Should someone ensure the continuing agreement of subjects to participate, as the research progresses?

8. Should the patient’s physician or other health care provider be consulted before any individual is invited to participate in the research? Is the research likely to interfere with ongoing therapy or regimens? Is it possible that the request to participate itself might provoke anxiety, stress, or other serious negative response?

APPLICABLE LAWS AND REGULATIONS

IRBs should be aware of any applicable law in their state, particularly those relating to consent by family members on behalf of persons incapable of consenting on their own. Note that consent to participation in research may differ from consent to medical treatment. In addition, it should be noted that some federal agencies (including components of the Department of Defense) prohibit the participation of mentally disabled persons in research conducted under their auspices.

Return to Top of Page

E. PRISONERS

INTRODUCTION

The involvement of prison inmates in research was once common because the stability of prison life (e.g., controlled diet, ready availability of subjects for follow-up) made prisons attractive research environments. More recently, however, ethicists and others concerned with the treatment of human participants in research recognized that the very fact of incarceration may make it difficult or impossible for prisoners to give voluntary, informed consent. In response to this growing concern, the National Commission for the Protection of Human Subjects was asked to consider the problem; the Commission issued its report and recommendations in 1976. In 1978, DHHS issued specific regulations governing research with prisoners [45 CFR 46 Subpart C]. The implementation of FDA regulations on research involving prisoners has been stayed until further notice [21 CFR 50 Subpart C]. Some federal agencies significantly limit the involvement of prisoners in biomedical research (e.g., Federal Bureau of Prisons).

DEFINITIONS

Minimal Risk: Risk of physical or psychological harm that is no greater in probability and severity than that ordinarily encountered in the daily lives, or in the routine medical, dental or psychological examinations of healthy persons [45 CFR 46.303(d)]. IRBs should note that this definition differs somewhat from that given for noninstitutionalized, competent adults [Federal Policy §___.102(i); 45 CFR 46.102(i)].

Prisoner: An individual involuntarily confined in a penal institution, including persons: (1) sentenced under a criminal or civil statute; (2) detained pending arraignment, trial, or sentencing; and (3) detained in other facilities (e.g., for drug detoxification or treatment of alcoholism) under statutes or commitment procedures providing such alternatives to criminal prosecution or incarceration in a penal institution [45 CFR 46.303(c)].

IRB CONSIDERATIONS

General Considerations. The first question IRBs must ask when a protocol proposes to use prison inmates as a study population is whether that population was chosen simply out of convenience to the investigator. Because the population is relatively stable and the life is routine, prisons have in the past seemed ideal environments in many ways for the conduct of certain types of research. Some procedures that would inconvenience free subjects are not a burden to prisoners. Since prison pay scales are notably lower than those in the free world, the cost of using prisoners as subjects may be less than using those who are not prisoners. And, unlike the general civilian population, they are all in one place. However, the nature of incarceration may conflict with the ethical principal of autonomy, captured in the Nuremberg Code provision requiring that the subject “be so situated as to be able to exercise free power of choice, without the intervention of any element of force, fraud, deceit, duress, over-reaching, or other ulterior form of constraint or coercion.”

The primary issue surrounding the participation of prisoners in research has always been whether prisoners have a real choice regarding their participation in research, or whether their situation prohibits the exercise of free choice. A secondary issue is whether confidentiality of participation and of data can be adequately maintained in the prison.

The circumstances common in prisons create environments in which the offer to participate in research is necessarily coercive or creates a undue influence in favor of participation. To the extent that living conditions in prison are bad and the provision of health care is minimal or even nonexistent, the lack of control allowed prisoners and the desire to obtain the advantages offered to those who agree to participate may preclude their ability to weigh fairly the risks and benefits involved in participation. For example, the investigator may propose to move the research participants to special units where they are given medical care and where the living conditions are better than those provided to the general prison population. Another coercive situation would be where prisoners must earn money to purchase the means by which to maintain their health and personal hygiene, and one way to earn that money is by participating in research. Other rewards for participation, such as offering parole or a reduction in sentence, would constitute an undue inducement. Even the opportunity to leave the prison cell and interact with people from outside the prison may act as an undue inducement to participate in research.

Nancy Dubler (1982) has described the prison setting as “inherently coercive.” She describes prisons as brutal and dangerous, “woefully overcrowded, understaffed, underprogrammed and ill-supported by any coherent philosophy of reform, or even punishment” [p. 10]. She provides the following quote from a report in a prison inmate magazine:

Louisiana pays its prisoners from two to five cents an hour for their labors, an amount grossly inadequate to meet their needs. To augment that income, many inmates sell their “plasma” twice weekly to the privately-owned plasma company located in the Main Prison, getting $9.50 each time. The process involves the plasma firm drawing a pint of blood from the inmate, extracting the plasma, then returning the “red blood” back to the inmate. Whenever the bag containing the donor’s blood accidentally bursts, preventing the return of the blood into the inmate, the firm’s policy is to suspend the inmate from the plasma program for six weeks to allow sufficient time for his blood cells to build back up. Such a suspension entails a total loss of $114 income for the inmate, money he would have earned during that six-week period.

But, as it turns out, the bursting of the blood bags of some donors weren’t (sic) always caused by accidents. According to information from inmates and security personnel, a number of inmate-employees of the plasma firm were threatening to deliberately bust the bags of homosexuals and inmates in protective custody units if the inmate-victim did not agree to “belong” to them. It was reported that such threats were also utilized to extort sex from them.

According to an informed source, some of the inmate-victims complained to the Warden’s office, providing names of those allegedly involved in the homosexual extortion scheme. And, in a move that caught the entire Main Prison by surprise, the Warden’s Office ordered the immediate transfer of nine inmate plasma workers out of the Main Prison to outcamps, all those believed to be involved. “I’ve been in this business for a long time, and I thought I knew all the prison games,” the source told The Angolite, shaking his head, “but this is a new one on me...’starving them out,’ they called it.”

In addition to problems of coercion and undue inducement, the involvement of prisoners in research raises questions of burden and benefit. Prisoners should neither bear an unfair share of the burden of participating in research, nor should they be excluded from its benefits, to the extent that voluntary participation is possible. Prisoners’ rights to self-determination (autonomy) should not be circumscribed more than required by applicable regulations (see below). IRBs should refrain from assuming, without cause, that prospective prisoner-subjects will lack the ability to make autonomous decisions about participation in research. To the extent that prisoner-subjects are found able to voluntarily consent to participation, and to the extent allowable under applicable regulations, prisoners should be allowed the opportunity to participate in potentially beneficial research.

Another question is whether prisoner-subjects can ethically be paid for participation, and if so, how much. In nonprison settings, paying subjects to participate in research is considered ethically acceptable, so long as it is commensurate with the discomfort and/or inconvenience involved. Paying prisoners the same amount that would be paid to nonprisoners may, however, be seen as unduly influential in a setting where inmates can earn only a small fraction of that amount for any other “work” activity. On the other hand, paying prisoners a fraction of what would be paid to nonprisoners can be seen as exploitative. One suggestion that has been offered is to require that investigators pay prisoners at the same rate as they would pay nonprisoners, but that individuals would receive an amount comparable to that paid for other prison tasks. The difference would be paid into a general prison fund, to be used, for instance, to subsidize the wages paid to all prisoners, or to be used for educational or recreational purposes (to be determined by the prison population, not the administrators). Alternatively, the difference could be paid into an escrow account, to be distributed to the prisoner upon release or to be paid to the prisoner’s family [Levine (1986), pp. 282-83; Veatch (1987), p. 60].

Finally, confidentiality is extremely difficult to maintain in an environment such as prisons in which there is no privacy. In prisons, people do not move about freely; the movements of prisoners are carefully tracked. When inmates are moved around (e.g., to go to a research appointment), everyone will know about it. Prison records, including medical records, are accessible to persons who in other settings would not have access to such personal information. Consider the inmate participating in HIV-related research. How will the sensitive nature of the research be kept secret? Before an IRB approves any research in prisons, the investigator must be able to ensure that the necessary confidentiality can and will be maintained so that the participants are not subjected to any risk from participation.

To protect prisoners from the exploitative conditions presented by these situations, DHHS issued regulations governing research with prisoners, limiting it to studies with an independent and valid reason for involving this particular population (e.g., studies of the effects of incarceration). These limitations were imposed in response to, but are more restrictive than, the recommendations of the National Commission. Writing about research on HIV infection and AIDS in prisons, Dubler and Sidel (1989) summarize the goals of protection of prisoners involved in research. They state that, “Inmates as a group need to be protected from research designs that can acquire the data through other routes and may present risks to inmates as a class. They need to be provided with access to clinical trials of new and innovative therapies that present the possibility of direct benefit to the subjects. They must be presented with the opportunity for informed choice when appropriate, despite recognition that the systematic deprivations and inherent coerciveness of the institutions...compromise the consent process” [p. 204].

Regulations. If a protocol involves the use of prisoners as subjects, both the general DHHS regulations governing research with human subjects and the special ones dealing specifically with prisoners apply. [See discussion in the Introduction to Chapter 6 on the question of applicability of DHHS regulations.] If, because of its nature, the IRB has reason to know that it will be reviewing protocols involving prisoners as subjects, IRB members should familiarize themselves with these regulations and discuss them before any actual prisoner protocols are presented.

DHHS regulations have special requirements regarding the membership of an IRB that reviews research involving prisoners [45 CFR 46.304]. At least one member of the IRB must be a prisoner or a prisoner representative with the appropriate background and experience to serve in that capacity. A majority of IRB members (exclusive of prison members), must have no other association, apart from IRB membership, with the prison(s) involved.

Only certain kinds of research conducted or supported by DHHS may involve prisoners as subjects: (1) studies (involving no more than minimal risk or inconvenience) of the possible causes, effects, and processes of incarceration and criminal behavior; (2) studies (involving no more than minimal risk or inconvenience) of prisons as institutional structures or of prisoners as incarcerated persons; (3) research on particular conditions affecting prisoners as a class (providing the Secretary, HHS, has consulted with appropriate experts and published [his or her] intent to support such research in the Federal Register); and (4) research involving a therapy likely to benefit the prisoner subject (and if the therapeutic research also involves nontherapeutic research with a control group, the Secretary, HHS, must also consult with appropriate experts and publish [his or her] intent to support the research in the Federal Register).

Much of the permissible research is behavioral. Biomedical research concerning, for example, the effects of limited exercise or prison diets on the overall physical condition of inmates may also be permitted, providing the research procedures present no more than minimal risk. IRBs should be alert to the possible risk of retaliation by other inmates or prison guards posed by a prisoner’s participation in a study of such topics as HIV infection or AIDS, rape, drug use, or violent behavior within the institution.

The IRB has additional responsibilities when reviewing research involving prisoners [45 CFR 46.305]. It must determine whether any advantages the prisoners may obtain through participation in the research are of sufficient magnitude to impair the inmates’ ability to choose to participate, given the institutional context of limited choice (advantage as compared to the general living conditions, medical care, quality of food, amenities, and opportunity for earnings in the prison) [45 CFR 46.305(a)(2)]. The IRB must also decide if the risks involved in the research are commensurate with risks that would be accepted by nonprisoner volunteers [45 CFR 305(a)(3)]. It must ensure that the procedures for selecting subjects are fair and immune from arbitrary intervention by prison authorities or prisoners [45 CFR 305(a)(4) ]. There must be adequate assurances that parole boards will not take a prisoner’s participation in research into account when making parole decisions, and each prisoner must be clearly informed in advance that participation will have not effect on his or her parole [45 CFR 46.305(a)(6)]. The research institution must thereafter certify to the Secretary, HHS, that these special responsibilities have been fulfilled [45 CFR 46.305(c)].

An understanding of the definition of minimal risk provided in 45 CFR 46 Subpart C is critical. The risks to which prisoners may be exposed by participating in the research is not compared with the risks “normally encountered...by prisoners,” but rather with risks “normally encountered in the daily lives, or in the routine medical, dental or psychological examination of healthy persons,” i.e., nonprisoners. Dubler and Sidel (1989) have argued that in assessing risk, IRBs:

1. Ought not to use the risks that face prisoners in the prison setting as the standard for acceptable risk;
2. Ought not to judge even apparently ordinary risks at face value [e.g., confidentiality in prison is impossible to maintain];
3. Ought to allow only risks that are commensurate with those accepted by nonprisoners [pp. 199-200].

IRB members should be aware of any state law governing research with prisoners. More than half the states have legislation or regulations restricting research with prisoners; prisoners incarcerated in non-federal penal institutions in states with no specific law regarding prison research will lack the protection provided by such restrictions; IRBs reviewing protocols that propose to involve subjects in such institutions should therefore, recognize the special protective role they play. IRBs in such situations would be well advised to study the recommendations of the National Commission for the Protection of Human Subjects on research with prisoners. These recommendations describe a series of considerations that balance the risks of research with the conditions of incarceration.

Regulations promulgated by the FDA [21 CFR 50 Subpart C] have been stayed until further notice. IRBs should check the status of the FDA regulations when reviewing research to which FDA regulations would apply.

The Federal Bureau of Prisons places special restrictions on research that takes place within the Bureau of Prisons. Those regulations are published at 28 CFR Part 512. The restrictions apply to any research involving inmates in the custody of the Attorney General, and assigned to the Bureau of Prisons, regardless of the institution in which the inmate is incarcerated (e.g., even if the inmate is resident in a state institution). Primarily, research within the Federal Bureau of Prisons is limited to research involving no more than minimal risk, and, where applicable, must be consistent with the Bureau of Prisons’ policy on medical experimentation and pharmaceutical testing [28 CFR 512.12]. Research proposals are reviewed by the Director, Bureau of Prisons, following review by the local institution and regional administrative units [28 CFR 512.14]. The policy on medical experimentation and pharmaceutical testing generally prohibits biomedical research and drug testing on its inmates, although individual prisoners in need of medical treatment and who qualify for experimental therapy may participate in DHHS-approved clinical trials “when recommended by the responsible physician and approved by the [Federal Bureau of Prisons’] Medical Director” [Federal Bureau of Prisons, Health Services Manual, Program Statement 6000.3, para. 6823]. For more information concerning biomedical research involving prisoners under the jurisdiction of the Federal Bureau of Prisons, contact:

Ms. Harriet Lebowitz
Office of Research and Evaluation
Federal Bureau of Prisons
Room 3007, 400 First Building
Washington, D.C. 20534
Tel: (202) 307-3871, ext. 120
Fax: (202) 307-5888

POINTS TO CONSIDER

1. Does the IRB have the necessary prisoner-related members?

2. Does the proposed research fall within one of the permissible categories of research with prisoners?

3. Is the use of prisoners as subjects justified?

4. Is there any evidence of duress, coercion, or undue influence in the particular prison(s) from which subjects will be recruited? (Does the prison facility meet all of the conditions set forth in applicable regulations?)

5. Are there any applicable state laws with which the IRB must comply?

APPLICABLE LAWS AND REGULATIONS

Federal policy for the protection of human subjects

21 CFR 50 Subpart C

[FDA: Regulations governing research with prisoners]

45 CFR 46 Subpart C

[DHHS: Additional protections pertaining to biomedical and
behavioral research involving prisoners as subjects]

28 CFR 512

[Department of Justice, Federal Bureau of Prisons: Research]

Federal Bureau of Prisons, Health Services Manual, Program Statement 6000.3

Regulations of the various components of the Defense Department

State statutes and regulations concerning research with prisoners

Return to Top of Page

 

 

 

F. TRAUMATIZED AND COMATOSE PATIENTS

INTRODUCTION

Research involving patients who require emergency treatment may involve the administration of an experimental emergency treatment or the close monitoring of a generally recognized emergency treatment. In either case, special problems of informed consent are raised.

OVERVIEW

Research involving subjects undergoing emergency care differs from clinical research in other settings because the patient’s capacity to provide informed consent is often severely compromised, and decisions about participation in research may have to be made too quickly to obtain permission from the patient’s legally authorized representative. The patient’s altered mental status may vary from one of confusion and disorientation to coma. Altered mental status may result from an accident or emergency condition, a physiological response such as shock or infection, a psychological response (anxiety, grief, or physical pain), or the effects of drugs.

Research involving emergency patients is further complicated because there are a variety of state laws concerning informed consent for emergency treatment that might be applied to research on therapy for emergency patients. DHHS regulations (and the Federal Policy) permit the waiver of informed consent requirements only in the case of research that presents no more than minimal risk [45 CFR 46.116]. FDA regulations, on the other hand, permit exception from the informed consent requirement for patients confronted by a life-threatening situation where there is no alternative method of approved or generally recognized therapy that provides an equal or greater likelihood of saving the subject’s life [21 CFR 50.23]. Some legal scholars have suggested that experimental emergency treatment might be given to a patient who cannot give informed consent if, in the opinion of the physician, it is the most promising treatment available. DHHS regulations say only that “nothing in these regulations is intended to limit the authority of a physician to provide emergency medical care, to the extent the physician is permitted to do so under applicable Federal, State, or local law” [45 CFR 46.116(f)].

See also Guidebook Chapter 3, Section B, “Informed Consent,” which discusses the circumstances under which the DHHS requirements for consent may be altered or waived, and Chapter 2, Section B, “Food and Drug Administration Regulations and Policies,” which addresses the distinction between DHHS and FDA regulations on waiver of IRB review, waiver of informed consent, and emergency use of a test article.

IRB CONSIDERATIONS

The risks and benefits of studies in emergency care may each vary from extremely high to negligible. At one extreme, where significant incapacity or death is almost certain, a new therapeutic measure may offer a reasonable chance for recovery, sustaining life, or preventing serious and permanent deficits. In other situations, the potential benefits and risks may be equally great; one may not “outweigh” the other. Drugs given in an effort to save the lives of trauma victims might do so at the risk of preserving those lives in a persistent vegetative state. Many studies involving emergency care may be almost without risk yet yield information useful in the treatment of the patient (e.g., monitoring certain physiological events by noninvasive means).

The IRB should ensure that the risks are minimized, the confidence in the anticipated benefits is justifiable, and the risks are reasonable in relation to the anticipated benefits. According to DHHS regulations (and the Federal Policy), IRBs may waive the informed consent requirements when the risks are no more than minimal, the research could not reasonably be carried out without waiving the requirement of informed consent, and such a waiver would not adversely affect the subject’s rights or welfare [45 CFR 46.116(d); Federal Policy §___.116(d)]. Subjects or their legally authorized representative should be provided with pertinent information when, and if, it becomes possible and appropriate. DHHS regulations and the Federal Policy preclude research presenting more than minimal risk without the subject’s legally valid consent unless it is possible to obtain the permission of the patient’s legally authorized representative. The mental state of family members in the emergency situation may, however, preclude good decision making. Further, it is often not possible to locate family members in time to make the decisions necessary in emergency care. IRBs and investigators should also note the distinction between “next-of-kin” and “legally authorized representative.” Although “consent” by next-of-kin is traditionally accepted by physicians treating incompetent or comatose patients, family members do not have clear legal authority to give such consent except in a few states having statutes or case law on the subject.

FDA regulations permit exception from the informed consent requirements when both the investigator and a physician not otherwise involved in the research certify in writing that: (1) the subject is confronted by a life-threatening situation necessitating the use of the test article; (2) informed consent cannot be obtained from the subject because of an inability to communicate with, or obtain legally effective consent from the subject; (3) there is not sufficient time to obtain consent from the subject’s legally authorized representative; and (4) there is no alternative method of approved or generally recognized therapy that provides an equal or greater likelihood of saving the life of the subject available [21 CFR 50.23]. Documentation of such circumstances must be submitted to an IRB within five working days.

In contrast, under the DHHS regulations, if prior informed consent is not possible, and the IRB has not waived the informed consent requirements (e.g., if the research involves greater than minimal risk), the patient should be excluded from the study and provided with standard care. In cases in which the requirement for emergency care is foreseeable and subjects can be identified in advance (e.g., a study to be performed after elective major surgery), informed consent might be obtained well before the surgery.

IRBs and investigators should note that where a patient requires emergency care, DHHS regulations requiring prior IRB review remain in effect. While the regulations do not “limit the authority of a physician to provide emergency medical care” [45 CFR 46.116(f)], they also do not permit research activities to begin as part of emergency medical care unless the research has received prior IRB review and approval [45 CFR 46.103(b); “Emergency Medical Care,” OPRR Reports (May 15, 1991)]. While such patients may receive emergency medical care, the patient may not be considered to be a research subject. “Such emergency care may not be claimed as research, nor may the outcome of such care be included in any report of a research activity” [OPRR Reports (May 15, 1991)].

In contrast, FDA regulations do allow for the emergency use of a test article, without prior IRB review and approval, so long as the emergency use is reported to the IRB within five working days of its occurrence. Any subsequent use of the test article is subject to IRB review [21 CFR 50.23; 21 CFR 56.104(c)]. The FDA’s regulations on emergency use of test articles is discussed in greater detail in Guidebook Chapter 2, Section B, “Food and Drug Administration Regulations and Policies.”

POINTS TO CONSIDER

1. Does the research pose more than minimal risk to subjects?

2. Do the anticipated benefits to the subjects justify proceeding with the research even though it is not possible to obtain their prior informed consent? (Proceeding with research without prior informed consent is acceptable only for minimal risk research under DHHS regulations and in life-threatening situations under FDA regulations.)

3. Is consent from the patient’s next-of-kin required? Is it sufficient? (Check if there are any applicable state laws on this subject.)

4. If a preliminary consent procedure is employed, what amount of time should reasonably be allowed to elapse before requiring that a valid consent be obtained or the subject be removed from the study?

5. Is there a need for additional monitoring, either of the consent process or the conduct of the research itself?

APPLICABLE LAWS AND REGULATIONS

21 CFR 50.23

[FDA: Informed consent]

Applicable state law concerning consent to experimental emergency medical treatment for persons incapable of consenting. Note that consent to medical treatment may differ from consent to research.

Return to Top of Page

G. TERMINALLY ILL PATIENTS

INTRODUCTION

Terminally ill patients are those who are deteriorating from a life-threatening disease or condition for which no effective standard treatment exists. It is generally considered unacceptable to ask such persons to participate in research for which alternative, not similarly burdened, populations of subjects exist. Nevertheless, it may often be necessary to involve terminally ill patients in research concerning their disease and its treatment. Further, terminally ill persons should not be excluded from research in which they may want to participate simply because of their status. One can imagine that altruism and a desire to bring good from adversity may well motivate persons suffering from life-threatening illnesses to become involved in biomedical or behavioral research. Still, terminally ill individuals are a vulnerable population of research subjects, and, therefore, require additional protection against coercion and undue influence [45 CFR 46.111(b)]. If an IRB regularly reviews research involving the terminally ill, it should include among its members one or more individuals knowledgeable about and experienced in working with these subjects [45 CFR 46.107].

With the appearance of HIV, concerns have emerged about circumstances under which persons with serious and life-threatening conditions may have access to research drugs through expanded access programs. The FDA’s Parallel Track program and Treatment IND regulations seek to address these concerns. [For a discussion of these two expanded availability mechanisms, see Guidebook Chapter 2, Section B, “Food and Drug Administration Regulations and Policies.”] IRBs have a role both in considering circumstances in which terminally ill persons are appropriately excluded from research because they are a vulnerable group, and in providing persons who have no therapeutic alternatives the opportunity to receive the possible benefits of experimental interventions. [See also Guidebook Chapter 5, Section F, “AIDS/HIV-Related Research;” 21 CFR 312.34; and Federal Register 57:13250-13259 (April 15, 1992).]

DEFINITIONS

Expanded Availability: Policy and procedure that permits individuals who have serious or life-threatening diseases for which there are no alternative therapies to have access to investigational drugs and devices that may be beneficial to them. Examples of expanded availability mechanisms include Treatment INDs, Parallel Track, and open study protocols.

Therapeutic Intent: The research physician’s intent to provide some benefit to improving a subject’s condition (e.g., prolongation of life, shrinkage of tumor, or improved quality of life, even though cure or dramatic improvement cannot necessarily be effected.) This term is sometimes associated with Phase 1 drug studies in which potentially toxic drugs are given to an individual with the hope of inducing some improvement in the patient’s condition as well as assessing the safety and pharmacology of a drug.

OVERVIEW

In many contexts, research on terminal illness and its treatment requires the involvement of terminally ill patients when alternative populations for study do not exist or when involving alternative populations would be ethically unjustifiable. Two important reasons for concern regarding research involving terminally ill persons are: (1) they tend to be more vulnerable to coercion or undue influence than healthy adult research subjects; and (2) research involving the terminally ill is likely to present more than minimal risk.

The risk of coercion and undue influence may be caused by a variety of factors. In addition to the fact that severe illness often affects a person’s competence, terminally ill patients may be vulnerable to coercion or undue influence because of a real or perceived belief that participation is necessary to receive continuing care from health professionals or because the receipt of any treatment is perceived as preferable to receiving no treatment. Although terminally ill patients should be protected from an understandable tendency to enroll in research under false hopes, IRBs should not take too protective an attitude toward competent patients simply because they are terminally ill. Some terminally ill patients may find participation in research a satisfying way of imparting some good to others out of their own misfortune.

It is important to distinguish between risks that may be justified by anticipated benefits for the research subjects and risks associated with procedures performed purely for research purposes. A particularly difficult issue relating to research involving terminally ill patients arises in connection with the conduct of Phase 1 drug trials in which the drugs involved are known to be particularly toxic (e.g., a new form of cancer chemotherapy). In some of these studies, any benefit to the subject is, at best, highly unlikely. Despite the “therapeutic intent” of the investigators to benefit the subject, subjects may in fact experience a decline in health status, no improvements in terms of quality of life, or lengthened life for only a short time. It is extremely important that prospective subjects be clearly informed of the nature and likelihood of the risks and benefits associated with this kind of research. The challenge to the investigator and the IRB is to provide patients with an accurate description of the potential benefits without engendering false hope. [See Ackerman (1990).]

The HIV epidemic has heightened awareness of mechanisms for including in research persons who have serious and life-threatening illness. Increasingly, individuals and advocacy groups have emphasized the need for opportunities for terminally ill persons to exercise their right of autonomy: to weigh themselves the risks and benefits of participating in research on drugs, even where relatively little is known about the safety or effectiveness of the drugs. Many desperately ill individuals would like to take investigational drugs that may not be available except through limited, well-controlled clinical trials because they are in the very early stages of development.

Although the HIV epidemic has created a demand for expanded access to investigational drugs, the issue is not new. In the 1970s, a number of physicians, generally at academic centers, had access to investigational drugs through protocols outside the controlled clinical trial prior to drug approval. This mechanism allowed these physicians to provide investigational drugs to persons without satisfactory alternative therapies, even though they were not part of a controlled trial and the drug was not yet approved. The drugs in these protocols were usually also under active development in controlled trials. A similar mechanism was developed to provide investigational drugs to persons with cancer. The FDA and the National Cancer Institute (NCI) developed a special category of drugs called “Group C.” Group C drugs may be provided by oncologists to appropriate cancer patients through protocols outside the controlled clinical trial prior to the drug approval. In 1987, the FDA initiated a regulation establishing the treatment investigational new drug application (Treatment IND), and in 1992, instituted a policy providing for a “parallel track” mechanism [21 CFR 312.34; Federal Register 57:13250-13259 (April 15, 1992)]. Under a Treatment IND protocol, eligible patients have access to investigational new drugs intended to treat serious or life-threatening diseases; Parallel Track protocols enable persons with AIDS or HIV-related diseases who cannot participate in clinical trials to have access to investigational drugs. [See Guidebook Chapter 2, Section B, “Food and Drug Administration Regulations and Policies,” for a discussion of expanded access mechanisms.]

IRB CONSIDERATIONS

IRBs should give research involving terminally ill individuals careful attention; they should also consider requiring special procedures for protecting the rights and well-being of these subjects. IRBs should satisfy themselves that the nature, magnitude, and probability of the risks and benefits of the research have been identified as clearly and as accurately as possible. Special attention should be paid to the consent process, both in terms of the accuracy of the information to be provided and the manner in which consent is sought. As a general rule, accurate information concerning eligibility for participation (i.e., diagnosis and prognosis), treatment options, and risks and benefits should be conveyed clearly and in a manner that will not either engender false hope or eliminate all hope.

IRBs must also consider including other information the patient might find relevant to making an informed decision to participate. For example, subjects should be told whether or not participation in the study is a condition for treatment at the institution; any costs to the patient of the research should be stated explicitly. IRBs should consider whether any payment might constitute an undue enticement, particularly if the subject population is economically disadvantaged. Patients should be provided with relevant information well in advance of making a decision about participation, and consultation with others such as family members, close friends, clergy, or medical consultants should be encouraged.

IRBs may also find it advisable to require that the clinical investigator be someone other than the patient’s physician, that emergency services be readily available, or that there be frequent monitoring of the progress of the research. Factors to consider in making such decision include: anticipated toxicity of the therapeutic interventions; extent to which subjects are likely to be debilitated by either their illness or their therapy; the remaining life expectancy of the subjects; and whether participation in the research would require a change in residence (e.g., from home or hospice to a hospital or research institution).

POINTS TO CONSIDER

1. Must the research involve terminally ill patients to achieve its objectives?

2. Is a clear explanation of the patient’s eligibility for the study provided?

3. Are specific treatment alternatives, including the option of no treatment, described?

4. Are the potential benefits and risks (and their probability) realistically and simply stated?

5. Are the ways in which participation may affect the patient’s lifestyle clearly described (e.g., “You will be hospitalized each month for 5-7 days.”)?

6. Is the patient assured that he or she can withdraw from the study at any time? If withdrawal from the research will result in a patient’s discharge from a research unit or end the patient’s access to health care that has been provided in conjunction with the research, is that fully explained?

7. Should a witness or patient advocate be present during consent negotiations?

8. Is there reason to require that the patient’s physician not be the clinical investigator?

9. If the research is done under a Treatment IND or other expanded access mechanism, is the lack of conclusive effectiveness data made clear? Are all costs to subjects of receiving a drug or device under an expanded availability mechanism clearly specified?

10. If a drug is administered at the community level, does the subject’s physician have access to information about the drug’s potential usefulness and potential risks?

APPLICABLE LAWS AND REGULATIONS

45 CFR 46

[DHHS: Protection of human subjects]

21 CFR 50

[FDA: Informed consent]

21 CFR 56

[FDA: IRB review and approval]

21 CFR 312

[FDA: New drugs for investigational use]

Federal Register 57:13250-13259 (April 15, 1992) [FDA: Parallel Track policy]

Return to Top of Page

H. ELDERLY/AGED PERSONS

INTRODUCTION

As the American population ages, research on the aging process and conditions and diseases that disproportionately affect the elderly has become increasingly important. The participation of older subjects in research poses several issues for IRBs; primary among them is the question of whether and when the elderly need special protections. IRBs must maintain the balance between the need for protection and the need to provide respect for persons.

IRB CONSIDERATIONS

Aside from the regulatory requirement that IRBs provide additional protections for specially vulnerable persons [Federal Policy §___.111], there are no specific regulations governing research with elderly subjects. It is generally agreed, however, that the elderly are, as a group, heterogenous and not usually in need of special protections, except in two circumstances: cognitive impairment and institutionalization. Under those conditions, the same considerations are applicable as with any other, nonelderly subject in the same circumstances.

There is no age at which prospective subjects should become ineligible to participate in research. Most older people are neither cognitively impaired nor live in institutional settings. Nevertheless, investigators may avoid elderly subjects because of difficulties in recruiting them to participate. Older persons tend to avoid research that interrupts their daily routine, is uncomfortable or inconvenient, or is not designed to provide direct benefits to them [Levine (1986), p. 85; Sachs and Cassel (1990), p. 236; Cassel (1985), p. 46]. Also, conducting research with older patients may be more difficult and more costly. Elderly persons may have hearing or vision problems and may therefore require more time to have the study explained to them. They also drop out of studies at a higher rate than do younger subjects, so that investigators may need to recruit more subjects initially to account for this possibility.

Despite these difficulties, the inclusion of older persons in the research enterprise is important. IRBs should ensure that where they are excluded or treated specially, older subjects are in need of protection and are not the object of disdain, stereotyping, or paternalism. Together, researchers and the IRB should enable older persons to share in the benefits and burdens of research.

IRBs should treat cognitive impairment in elderly subjects as they would cognitive impairment in any prospective subject. [See Guidebook Chapter 6, Section D, “Cognitively Impaired.”] The subject population should comprise cognitively impaired persons only under the following circumstances: when competent subjects are not appropriate for the study; if the study is related to a problem unique to persons with that disability; and if the study involves minimal risk [Annas and Glantz (1986), p. 1157].

The use of age as the criterion of ability to consent and therefore participate in research is not valid. Studies have shown that education, health status, and inadequate communication about the research rather than age contribute to lack of comprehension and recall [Sachs and Cassel (1990), pp. 235-36]. While it is recognized that memory may be a problem for some elderly subjects (thus putting into question their ability to provide continuing consent), the question for the IRB is whether, despite some impairment to competence, subjects can make reasonable choices. It has been suggested that in order to screen subjects for sufficient comprehension and recall, a two-part consent process be used, where the second part involves a test of the subject’s comprehension and recall of the information presented in the first part. Repeated tests have been found to improve recall. Prospective subjects who do not remember the important facts about participation in the research after repeated testing should not be included in the study [Levine (1986), p. 85; Sachs and Cassel (1990), pp. 235-236].

In the past, persons in nursing homes or other institutions have been selected as subjects because of their easy accessibility. It is now recognized, however, that conditions in institutional settings increase the chances for coercion and undue influence because of the lack of freedom inherent in such situations. Research in these settings should therefore be avoided, unless the involvement of the institutional population is necessary to the conduct of the research (e.g., the disease or condition is endemic to the institutional setting, persons who suffer from the disease or condition reside primarily in institutions, or the study focuses on the institutional setting itself). [See Guidebook Chapter 6, Section D, “Cognitively Impaired” for a discussion of the problems of research involving institutionalized subjects.] Annas and Glantz (1986) suggest that “a nursing home council, composed primarily of residents, should review and approve any protocol before the research can be conducted at their facility. Research that may seem trivial to us in terms of risk, discomfort, disorientation, or dehumanizing effects may not seem so trivial to this vulnerable and often frightened population” [p. 1157].

POINTS TO CONSIDER

1. Does the proposed consent process provide mechanisms for determining the adequacy of prospective subjects’ comprehension and recall?

2. How will subjects’ competence to consent be determined?

3. Will the research take place in an institutional setting? Has the possibility of coercion and undue influence been sufficiently minimized?

APPLICABLE LAWS AND REGULATIONS

45 CFR 46

[DHHS: Protection of human subjects]

State and local laws regarding research involving institutionalized individuals

Return to Top of Page

I. MINORITIES

INTRODUCTION

The participation in research by members of racial and ethnic minority groups raises concerns about appropriate levels of inclusion and generalizability of study results; the issues are parallel to those raised with respect to the inclusion of women in studies. [See Guidebook Chapter 6, Section B, “Women.”] In addition, the involvement of minorities raises concerns about the selection of subjects, the possibility of special vulnerability on the part of some prospective subjects, and about consent and the relative strengths or weaknesses of vulnerable groups in the consent process.



IRB CONSIDERATIONS

The federal regulations require the equitable selection of subjects [Federal Policy ___.111(a)(3)]. In addition, NIH requires that applicants for all research grants, cooperative agreements, and contracts involving human subjects include minorities (and women) in study populations “so that research findings can be of benefit to all persons at risk of the disease, disorder or condition under study; special emphasis should be placed on the need for inclusion of minorities and women in studies of diseases, disorders and conditions which disproportionately affect them.” Investigators must provide a “clear compelling rationale for their exclusion or underrepresentation” [PHS Grant Application form 398, pp. 21-22]. The complete text of the policy and discussion of the issue of inclusion of women and minorities in study populations is provided in the Guidebook in Chapter 6, Section B, “Women.”

The inclusion of minorities in research is important, both to ensure that they receive an equal share of the benefits of research and to ensure that they do not bear a disproportionate burden. Most diseases affect all population groups, minority and nonminority alike. For generalizability purposes, investigators must include the widest possible range of population groups. Sometimes, however, minorities are subject to a differential risk. Some research, for example, relates to conditions that specifically affect various minority groups (e.g., sickle cell anemia or Tay Sachs disease), so that involvement of the relevant minority groups is imperative. Other research focuses on characteristics of diseases or effectiveness of therapies in particular populations (e.g., HIV transmission, treatment for hypertension), and may also concern conditions or disorders that disproportionately affect certain racial or ethnic groups. Exclusion or inappropriate representation of these groups, by design or inadvertence, would be unjust. Further, to the extent that participation in research offers direct benefits to the subjects (in HIV research, for example, the receipt of a promising new drug), underrepresentation of minorities denies them, in a systematic way, the opportunity to benefit. A glaring example of abuse of minority populations’ bearing the burden of research can be found in the Tuskegee study, in which a group of African-American men suffering from syphilis were left untreated, despite the availability of penicillin, in order to study the natural course of the disease.

The manner in which subjects are selected bears directly on the problem of inclusion of minorities. The choice of a geographic area for recruitment may affect the representation of racial and ethnic groups in study populations. Also, to the extent that minorities are reliant on public rather than private health care systems, recruitment of subjects from private physicians will tend to exclude minorities and recruitment from public health clinics will tend to overinclude them. In fact, recruiting subjects from any health care system assumes that appropriate subjects have access to and exercise their ability to access a health care system, which may contribute to the homogeneity of the study population. Some writers have suggested that investigators change recruitment strategies so that they recruit subjects through community-based institutions such as churches and neighborhood organizations, rather than solely through health care institutions. In many studies, several institutions collaborate, thereby enrolling subjects from different geographic locations. Such collaborations may also provide a mechanism for ensuring appropriate representation of women and minorities in the study population.

One justification that is offered for research with homogeneous populations is that it is a more simple, less costly way to conduct clinical trials. The more diverse the study population, the larger the subject pool must be (to achieve statistical significance when controlling for differences in race, gender, and ethnicity) and the more variables must be accounted for in analyzing the data. Nonetheless, when homogeneous populations are used, study results are then limited in their applicability to the precise population involved in the study, and may, in fact, hide inaccuracies.

Research designs that include diverse study populations are, therefore, highly desirable. IRBs should require investigators to justify protocols that call for homogeneous study populations. They should also be aware of the implications of various recruiting strategies, and be prepared to suggest alternative recruitment methods so as to ensure an appropriately diverse or focused subject population. In doing so, the IRB should also be aware of the special needs of prospective subjects, such as the provision of child care or transportation.

In addition to ensuring adequate appropriate representation of minorities in study populations (and guarding against inappropriate overburdening of minorities), IRBs must ensure that any special vulnerabilities of subjects are accounted for and handled appropriately. To the extent that prospective minority study populations are also economically or educationally disadvantaged, IRBs should safeguard their rights and welfare by making sure that any possible coercion or undue influence is eliminated (e.g., compensation that is not commensurate with the risk, discomfort, or inconvenience involved, or recruiting in institutional settings where voluntary participation might be compromised).

IRBs should also safeguard the consent process (and, indeed, the entire research relationship) to ensure open and free communication between the researcher and the prospective subject. Consent documents must be written in language easily understandable to subjects; the possibility of illiteracy should be accounted for, as should the need for communicating in foreign languages. The informed consent documents should be available in English and other languages as appropriate to the subject population(s). Foreign language consent documents should be developed using quality control procedures such as translation from English to the other language and then back to English, to ensure that the information is correctly conveyed. The role of cultural norms of subjects should also be addressed [Federal Policy ___.111(b)]. The involvement of representatives from the target population(s) may also be pertinent to IRB review.

IRBs should keep in mind that the goal here is to ensure that minorities share fairly the benefits and burdens of the research enterprise. In offering protection, however, IRBs should avoid paternalism and stereotyping.

POINTS TO CONSIDER

1. Is the subject population appropriately drawn? Will minority subjects likely be appropriately and adequately represented? If not, is the homogeneity of the study population justified?

2. Are subject recruitment strategies appropriate for obtaining a diverse subject population?

3. Have the special needs of prospective subjects been addressed (e.g., child care, transportation)?

4. Has the possibility of undue influence or coercion been eliminated?

5. Does the proposed consent process ensure open and effective communication between the researcher and prospective subjects? Are the consent documents written in language that will be easily accessible to subjects? Are documents in foreign languages necessary? Is foreign language facility on the part of the research staff necessary (both for obtaining consent and conducting the research)?

APPLICABLE LAWS AND REGULATIONS

Federal Policy ___.111

[Criteria for IRB approval of research]

NIH policy concerning inclusion of women and minorities in study populations. NIH Guide for Grants and Contracts 20 (No. 32, August 23, 1991): 1-3. The policy also appears in the application packet for Public Health Service Grants, form PHS 398, pp. 21-22, and in NIH Requests for Proposals (RFPs).

Application for Continuation of a Public Health Service Grant, form 2590, pp. 7-9 and Form Page 7.

Return to Top of Page

J. STUDENTS, EMPLOYEES, AND NORMAL VOLUNTEERS

INTRODUCTION

The involvement of students, employees, and normal volunteers in research may present special concerns with which IRBs should be familiar. The federal regulations do not provide explicit protections for subjects in these categories.

IRB CONSIDERATIONS

Normal Volunteers. Strange as it may seem at first, special concerns surround the involvement of normal (i.e., healthy) persons who volunteer to participate in research. Primarily, the principles involved are beneficence and respect for persons. In the Belmont Report, the National Commission for the Protection of Human Subjects of Biomedical and Behavioral Research stated the two general rules that describe beneficent actions as: (1) do not harm; and (2) maximize possible benefits and minimize possible harms. Volunteers for whom no therapeutic benefit can result from participation in research should, therefore, be exposed to risks that are minimized to the greatest extent possible. While the minimization of risks is an important requisite for any research involving human participants, the altruistic motivation of the normal volunteer’s agreement to participate (i.e., of contributing to scientific knowledge for the benefit of society) heightens the concern for the risks to which such participants should ethically be exposed.

The principle of respect for persons requires that research participants are, where capable of doing so, allowed to act autonomously and to express their right of self-determination. These principles are effectuated through the process of informed consent, which involves providing subjects with all relevant information about the study, including the risks and benefits involved, in clear and simple language, and ensuring that the information is understood and appreciated. Furthermore, the agreement to participate must be voluntary; the consent negotiations must be free from elements of coercion or undue inducement to participate. In research involving normal volunteers, particularly where the research involves more than minimal risk, IRBs must ensure that any monetary payments to subjects are not so great as to constitute an undue inducement. This issue may be particularly difficult for IRBs to deal with. Since subjects who volunteer to participate in such studies are usually compensated for their time and discomfort, IRBs should seriously scrutinize the payment schedules to ensure that any compensation offered is commensurate with the time, discomfort, and risk involved. Even so, where a research procedure involves serious discomfort and/or the real, though slight, possibility of serious harm (e.g., studies that involve the insertion and positioning of catheters in veins or the heart), one can easily imagine that the motivation of persons who volunteer to participate may be monetary. IRBs should pay particular attention to the proposed study population and whether it may comprise persons who are likely to be vulnerable to coercion or undue influence, such as persons who are educationally or economically disadvantaged. The federal regulations require that IRBs employ special safeguards under such circumstances [Federal Policy §___.111(b); 45 CFR 46.111(b)].

One area where normal volunteers are employed in research is in Phase 1 drug trials. The justification for the involvement of normal, healthy subjects is the need for volunteers whose experience with the trial materials is more easily analyzed because of the existence of fewer confounding factors. While Phase 1 trials are the first use of experimental drugs and devices in humans, preliminary studies involving animals provide investigators with data indicating a high likelihood of safe use in humans. Studies have indicated that the risk of injury from participating in Phase 1 studies is small, about the same as the risk of being injured while working as an office secretary [Levine (1982)]. The likelihood of risk, including the availability of animal data, should be scrutinized by IRBs.

Normal volunteers, like students and employees, should be recruited through general announcements or advertisements, rather than through individual solicitations. Personal solicitations increase the likelihood that participation will be the result of undue influence, either because of the relationship between the recruiter and the prospective subject, or methods of communication employed by the recruiter that may act to persuade prospective subjects to participate, thus compromising the voluntariness of the agreement to participate.

Investigators and IRBs should carefully consider what will happen if and when a normal volunteer should become sick or be injured during the research. As with any research involving human subjects, such issues should be clearly spelled out in the informed consent document, and should be reviewed carefully with the prospective subject. For example, subjects should be told: whether any medical treatments will be made available should injury occur and, if so, what they consist of; whom to contact should a research-related injury occur; and that they may discontinue participation at any time without penalty or loss of benefits to which they would otherwise be entitled [Federal Policy §___.116(a)(6-8); 45 CFR 46.116(a)(6-8)]. In addition, where appropriate subjects should be told whether they will be dropped from the study in the event of injury or illness, and whether they will be required to pay for treatment of research-related injuries or illness [Federal Policy §___.116(b)(2-3); 45 CFR 46(b)(2-3)]. Where illness in healthy volunteers does occur, particularly during a drug study, investigation by an independent physician may be warranted. [See Fazackerley, Randall, and Pleuvry (1987).]

The issues raised by the involvement of healthy subjects in genetic research is discussed in Guidebook Chapter 5, Section H, “Human Genetic Research.”

Students. Universities, and the association of investigators with them, provide investigators with a ready pool of research subjects: students. Many IRBs have faced the question of whether and in what way students may participate in research. Two questions that have been posed are whether students - medical students, in particular - should be allowed to participate in biomedical research (and whether special protections should be adopted to restrict their participation), and whether participation in research can appropriately be included as a course component for course credit. The latter practice is commonly employed in psychology departments.

The problem with student participation in research conducted at the university is the possibility that their agreement to participate will not be freely given. Students may volunteer to participate out of a belief that doing so will place them in good favor with faculty (e.g., that participating will result in receiving better grades, recommendations, employment, or the like), or that failure to participate will negatively affect their relationship with the investigator or faculty generally (i.e., by seeming “uncooperative,” not part of the scientific community). Prohibiting all student participation in research, however, may be an over protective reaction. An alternative way to protect against coercion is to require that faculty-investigators advertise for subjects generally (e.g., through notices posted in the school or department) rather than recruit individual students directly. As with any research involving a potentially vulnerable subject population, IRBs should pay special attention to the potential for coercion or undue influence and consider ways in which the possibility of exploitation can be reduced or eliminated.

Whether medical students in particular require special protections has been hotly debated. Some universities have either prohibited their participation or severely restricted it to, for instance, research involving minimal risk and minimal interruption of time. Strong arguments have been made against such protections, including claims that as future physicians (and possibly researchers) they may be obliged to participate. Angoff has argued that protecting medical students to a greater degree than protecting other normal volunteers smacks of elitism. Angoff (1985) states, “One may wonder why it is acceptable to ask the masses to accept risk in the name of science but not the very people whose futures are linked to the successful perpetuation of biomedical research” [p. 10]. Nolan (1979), Levine (1984), Angoff (1985), and others have argued that medical students are in a particularly good position to participate in some biomedical research because of their ability to comprehend the procedures involved in studies and evaluate the risks involved, which may not be possible to achieve with other normal volunteers. Angoff and others have also argued that it is acceptable to pay medical students as one would any research participant.

Requiring participation in research for course credit (or extra credit) is also controversial, though common in the social and behavioral sciences. The justification offered for requiring student participation is educational benefit [Gamble (1982); Cohen (1982)]. Clearly, however, participation of students is seen by faculty-investigators as necessary to the conduct of their research. Grant budgets often do not allow investigators to pay subjects; giving course credit or extra credit is a means of obtaining sufficient participation rates. Again, the issue for IRBs is whether such arrangements for selecting subjects is fair and noncoercive.

Participation in studies might be mandatory or for extra credit. Students in beginning psychology courses, for instance, might be required to serve as subjects for a given number of hours of research or in a given number of research projects. Or they might be given the option of participating for additional grade credit. Several mechanisms have been suggested for diminishing or eliminating the coercive aspect of student participation for course credit that IRBs might find useful. Gamble (1982) describes a departmental guideline for research involving students where extra credit is offered for participation. Students are to be given other options for fulfilling the research component that were comparable in terms of time, effort, and educational benefit: “for example, short papers, special projects, book reports, and brief quizzes on additional readings” [p. 7]. He raises concerns about the comparability of such alternatives with participating in research (e.g., that if they participate in studies, all they have to do is show up and spend the time, but if they choose to write a paper, it gets graded, and if they do extra readings, they have to be tested on them), and concludes that paying student subjects as researchers would any other subject is the only way to protect students’ freedom of choice to participate. Cohen (1982) describes a similar policy that seems to meet these concerns. To fulfill the research component, students can either participate in five hours of research, write a brief research paper, or attend faculty research colloquia. The paper is not graded, and students who attend the colloquia have only to show up. If students do choose to participate in studies, the policy seeks to increase the likelihood that participation is freely chosen by requiring: that students be given several studies to choose from and may not be required to volunteer for any particular study; that the studies must not involve more than minimal risk; that students can withdraw from the study at any time without losing the extra credit [p. 11].

Another concern raised by the involvement of students as subjects is confidentiality. As with research involving human subjects generally, IRBs should be aware that research involving the collection of data on sensitive subjects such as mental health, sexual activity, or the use of illicit drugs or alcohol presents risks to subjects of which they should be made aware and from which they should be protected, to the greatest extent possible. The close environment of the university amplifies this problem.

Where students are likely to be participating in research, IRBs should consider including a student member or consulting with students where appropriate.

Employees. The issues with respect to employees as research subjects are essentially identical to those involving students as research subjects: coercion or undue influence, and confidentiality. As medical students have seemed ideal subjects by biomedical researchers, employees of drug companies have been seen by investigators as ideal subjects in some ways, because of their ability to comprehend the protocol and to understand the importance of the research and compliance with the protocol. Meyers (1979) provides a good summary of the structure of employee volunteer research programs. As student participation raises questions of the ability to exercise free choice because of the possibility that grades or other important factors will be affected by decisions to participate, employee research programs raise the possibility that the decision will affect performance evaluations or job advancement. It may also be difficult to maintain the confidentiality of personal medical information or research data when the subjects are also employees, particularly when the employer is also a medical institution [Meyers (1979)].

APPLICABLE LAWS AND REGULATIONS

45 CFR 46

[DHHS: Protection of human subjects]

21 CFR 50

[FDA: Informed consent]

21 CFR 56

[FDA: IRB review and approval]

Return to Top of Page

K. INTERNATIONAL RESEARCH

INTRODUCTION

It is important that all research with human subjects adequately protect the rights and welfare of the subjects. All human subjects research in which American investigators are involved, and which would be subject to the federal regulations if it were conducted wholly within the United States, must comply with the federal regulations for the protection of human subjects in all material respects.

IRB CONSIDERATIONS

The regulations recognize that “the procedures normally followed in the foreign countries [in which the research will take place] may differ from those set forth in this policy” [Federal Policy §___.101(h); 45 CFR 46.101(h)]. Research may be approved, therefore, if “the procedures prescribed by the [foreign] institution afford protections that are at least equivalent to those provided in this policy.” The foreign country’s procedures may then be substituted for the procedures required by the federal regulations. Approval of the substitution is to be given by the relevant federal department or agency head after review of the foreign procedures; notice of actions taken on such reviews are to be published in the Federal Register (or elsewhere, as provided for in department or agency procedures). [Note that the FDA has not adopted this provision for research that it regulates. All FDA-funded research, however, must comply with both DHHS and FDA regulations.]

The procedure for approving DHHS-supported research with a foreign component begins with the domestic institution with which the U.S. investigator(s) are affiliated. If the U.S. institution has an approved MPA on file with DHHS, the proposed research must be reviewed and approved by the institution’s IRB before submission for funding, as with any research involving human subjects. If DHHS funds the research, each foreign institution should, upon request, submit an appropriate Assurance to OPRR. Since, at the present time, no international code prescribes exactly the same procedures for protecting human subjects as do the U.S. regulations, OPRR reviews the actual procedures detailed by the foreign institution as the primary basis for negotiating acceptable Assurances. International codes will, however, be taken into consideration in the negotiations. If the institution’s practices are not equivalent to the U.S. regulations, OPRR can require that particular procedures be followed before recommending approval of the substitution.

If the U.S. institution holds an MPA, but the research is funded by a non-DHHS source, DHHS is less involved in review of the protocols for human subjects protections. Rather, as required by 45 CFR 46.103, the MPA-holding institution retains responsibility for protecting the rights and welfare of all human subjects involved in research under the institution’s auspices.

One difficult issue is determining what constitutes “protections that are at least equivalent” to the federal regulations. In the case of DHHS, this determination is made by OPRR. The broad policy outlines of international standards, such as the Declaration of Helsinki or the Nuremberg Code, are a starting place, but are not alone sufficient. Written descriptions of the specific procedural implementation of such policies that have been adopted by the foreign institution are required.

Departments and agencies other than DHHS follow different procedures for reviewing and approving research with foreign components. IRBs should consult the particular department or agency involved. [See list of persons to contact in Appendix 3.]

APPLICABLE LAWS AND REGULATIONS

Federal Policy §___.101(h)

[To what does this policy apply (foreign research)]

45 CFR 46.101(h)

[DHHS: To what does this policy apply? (foreign research)]

Return to Top of Page

SUGGESTIONS FOR FURTHER READING

A. Fetuses and Human In Vitro Fertilization

  • Baron, C. H. “Fetal Research: The Question in the States.” Hastings Center Report 15 (No. 2, April 1985): 12-16.
  • Bleich, J. David. “Fetal Tissue Research: Jewish Tradition and Public Policy.” Tradition: A Journal of Orthodox Jewish Thought 24 (No. 4, Summer 1989): 69-90.
  • Burtchaell, James Tunstead. “University Policy on Experimental Use of Aborted Fetal Tissue.” IRB 10 (No. 4, July/August 1988): 7-11.
  • Burtchaell, James Tunstead. “The Use of Aborted Fetal Tissue in Research: A Rebuttal.” IRB 11 (No. 2, March/April 1989): 9-12. Rebuttal to Benjamin Freedman, “The Ethics of Using Human Fetal Tissue,” IRB 10 (No. 6, November/December 1988): 1-4; and to John Robertson, “Fetal Tissue Transplant Research is Ethical,” IRB 10 (No. 6, November/December 1988): 5-8.
  • Caplan, Arthur L. “Arguing with Success: Is In Vitro Fertilization Research or Therapy?” In Beyond Baby M: Ethical Issues in New Reproductive Techniques, edited by Dianne M. Bartels et al., pp. 149-170. Clifton, NJ: Humana Press, 1990.
  • Childress, James F. “Ethics, Public Policy, and Human Fetal Tissue Transplantation.” Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 1 (No. 2, June 1991): 93-121.
  • Fine, Alan. “The Ethics of Fetal Tissue Transplants.” Hastings Center Report 18 (No. 3, June/July 1988): 5-8.
  • Fletcher, John C. “Ethical Issues in Clinical Trials of First Trimester Prenatal Diagnosis.” In Chorionic Villus Sampling: Fetal Diagnosis of Genetic Diseases in the First Trimester, edited by Bruno Brambati, Giuseppe Simoni, and Sergio Fabro, pp. 275-301. New York: Marcel Dekker, 1986.
  • Fletcher, John C. and Jonsen, Albert. “Ethical Considerations in Fetal Treatment.” In The Unborn Patient: Prenatal Diagnosis and Treatment, 2d ed., edited by Michael R. Harrison, Mitchell S. Golbus and Roy A. Filly, pp. 14-18. Philadelphia: Saunders, 1991.
  • Fletcher, John C., and Schulman, J. D. “Fetal Research: The State of the Question.” Hastings Center Report 15 (No. 2, April 1985): 6-12.
  • Freedman, Benjamin. “The Ethics of Using Human Fetal Tissue.” IRB 10 (No. 6, November/December 1988): 1-4. Response to James Tunstead Burtchaell, “Case Study: University Policy on Experimental Use of Aborted Fetal Tissue.” IRB 10 (No. 4, July/August 1988): 7-11.
  • Giesen, Dieter. “Developing Ethical Public Policy on Reproduction and Prenatal Research: Whose Interests Deserve What Protection?” Medicine and Law 8 (No. 6, 1989): 553-565.
  • Harrison, Michael R.; Golbus, Mitchell S.; and Filly, Roy A., eds. The Unborn Patient: Prenatal Diagnosis and Treatment. 2d ed. Philadelphia: Saunders, 1991.
  • Holder, Angela Roddey. “Fetal Research.” In Legal Issues in Pediatrics and Adolescent Medicine, 2d ed., by Angela Roddey Holder, pp. 50-81. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1985.
  • Jones, D.G. “Brain Birth and Personal Identity.” Journal of Medical Ethics 15 (No. 4, December 1989): 173-178.
  • Jonsen, Albert R. “Transplantation of Fetal Tissue: An Ethicist’s Viewpoint.” Clinical Research 36 (No. 3, April 1988): 215-219.
  • Levine, Robert J. “Fetal Research: The Underlying Issue.” Scientific American 261 (No. 2, August 1989): 112.
  • Levine, Robert J. “An IRB-Approved Protocol on the Use of Human Fetal Tissue.” IRB 11 (No. 2, March/April 1989): 7-8.
  • Levine, Robert J. Ethics and Regulation of Clinical Research. 2d ed. Baltimore: Urban and Schwarzenberg, 1986. See Chapter 13, “The Fetus and the Embryo.”
  • Mahowald, Mary B.; Silver, Jerry; and Ratcheson, Robert A. “The Ethical Options In Transplanting Fetal Tissue.” Hastings Center Report 17 (No. 1, February 1987): 9-15.
  • Mason, John Kenyon. “Fetal Experimentation.” In Medico-Legal Aspects of Reproduction and Parenthood, edited by John Kenyon Mason, pp. 168-186. Brookfield, VT: Gower, 1990.
  • Murray, Thomas H. “Ethical Issues in Fetal Surgery.” Bulletin of the American College of Surgeons 70 (No. 6, June 1985): 6-10.
  • Nolan, Kathleen. “Genung ist Genung: A Fetus Is Not a Kidney.” Hastings Center Report 18 (No. 6, December 1988): 13-19.
  • Ramsey, Paul. The Ethics of Fetal Research. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1975.
  • Robertson, John A. “Fetal Tissue Transplant Research is Ethical.” IRB 10 (No. 6, November/December 1988): 5-8. Response to James Tunstead Burtchaell, “University Policy on Experimental Use of Aborted Fetal Tissue.” IRB 10 (No. 4, July/August 1988): 7-11.
  • Robertson, John A. “Rights, Symbolism, and Public Policy in Fetal Tissue Transplants.” Hastings Center Report 18 (No. 6, December 1988): 5-12.
  • Robertson, John A. “The Right to Procreate and In Vitro Fertilization.” Journal of Legal Medicine 3 (1982): 333-366.
  • Sass, H.M. “Brain Life and Brain Death: A Proposal for a Normative Agreement.” Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 14 (No. 1, February 1989): 45-59.
  • Silverman, William A. “Human Experimentation in Perinatology.” Clinics in Perinatology 14 (No. 2, June 1987): 403-416.
  • Singer, Peter, and Kuhse, Helga. “The Ethics of Embryo Research.” Law, Medicine and Health Care 14 (Nos. 3-4, September 1986): 133-138.
  • Strauss, R.P., and Davis, J.U. “Prenatal Detection and Fetal Surgery of Clefts and Craniofacial Abnormalities in Humans: Social and Ethical Issues.” Cleft Palate Journal 27 (No. 2, April 1990): 176-182. Discussion, pp. 182-183.
  • Terry, Nicolas P. “’Alas! Poor Yorick,’ I Knew Him Ex Utero: The Regulation of Embryo and Fetal Experimentation and Disposal in England and the United States.” Vanderbilt Law Review 39 (No. 3, April 1986): 419-470.
  • Thomas, Adrian K. “Human Embryo Experimentation and Surrogacy.” The Medical Journal of Australia 153 (No. 7, October 1, 1990): 369-371.
  • U.S. Congress. House. Committee on Energy and Commerce. Subcommittee on Health and the Environment. “Fetal Tissue Transplantation Research.” Hearing, April 2, 1990. Washington, D.C.: U.S. Government Printing Office, 1990. 220 p. Serial No. 101-135. Includes a copy of the first volume of the December 1988 report of the National Institutes of Health’s Human Fetal Tissue Transplantation Research Panel.
  • U.S. Department of Health and Human Services. Public Health Service. National Institutes of Health. “Moratorium on Certain Fetal Tissue Research.” NIH Guide for Grants and Contracts 17 (Special Notice May 8, 1988)(1988a).
  • U.S. Department of Health and Human Services. Public Health Service. National Institutes of Health. Report of the Human Fetal Tissue Transplantation Research Panel. II Vols. Bethesda, MD: National Institutes of Health, 1988b.
  • U.S. Department of Health, Education and Welfare. Ethics Advisory Board. Report and Conclusions: HEW Support of Research Involving Human In Vitro Fertilization and Embryo Transfer. Washington, D.C.: U.S. Government Printing Office, May 4, 1979. Reprinted in Federal Register 44 (June 18, 1979): 35033.
  • U.S. Department of Health, Education and Welfare. Ethics Advisory Board. Report and Recommendations: HEW Support of Fetoscopy. Washington, D.C.: U.S. Government Printing Office, 1979. Reprinted in Federal Register 44 (August 14, 1979): 47732.
  • U.S. National Commission for the Protection of Human Subjects of Biomedical and Behavioral Research. Report and Recommendations: Research on the Fetus. Washington, D.C.: U.S. Government Printing Office, 1975. DHEW Publication No. (OS) 76-127.
  • U.S. National Commission for the Protection of Human Subjects of Biomedical and Behavioral Research. Appendix: Research on the Fetus. Washington, D.C.: U.S. Government Printing Office, 1975. DHEW Publication No. (OS)76-128.
  • Vawter, Dorothy E. et al. The Use of Human Fetal Tissue: Scientific, Ethical, and Policy Concerns C A Report of Phase I of an Interdisciplinary Research Project Conducted by the Center for Biomedical Ethics. Minneapolis: Center for Biomedical Ethics, University of Minnesota, January 1990.
  • Villanova Law Review. “Symposium: Research on the Fetus.” 22 (No. 2, 1977): 297-417. Collection of papers presented at symposium.
  • Walters, LeRoy. “Human In Vitro Fertilization: A Review of the Ethical Issues.” Hastings Center Report 9 (No. 4, August 1979): 23-43.

B. Women

  • Dresser, Rebecca. “Wanted, Single, White Male for Medical Research.” Hastings Center Report 22 (No. 1, January/February 1992): 24-29.
  • Halbreich, Uriel, and Carson, Stanley W. “Drug Studies in Women of Childbearing Age: Ethical and Methodological Considerations.” Journal of Clinical Psychopharmacology 9 (No. 5, October 1989): 328-333.
  • Holmes, Helen Bequaert. “Can Clinical Research be Both Ethical and Scientific? A Commentary Inspired by Rosser and Marquis.” Hypatia 4 (No. 2, Summer 1989): 156-168.
  • Kinney, E.L. et al. “Underrepresentation of Women in New Drug Trials: Ramifications and Remedies.” Annals of Internal Medicine 95 (No. 4, October 1981): 495-499.
  • Levine, Carol. “Women and HIV/AIDS Research: The Barriers to Equity.” IRB 13 (No. 1-2, January-April 1991): 18-22.
  • Rosser, Sue V. “Re-Visioning Clinical Research: Gender and the Ethics of Experimental Design.” Hypatia 4 (No. 2, Summer 1989): 125-139.
  • U.S. Department of Health and Human Services. Public Health Service. Food and Drug Administration. General Considerations for the Clinical Evaluation of Drugs in Infants and Children. Washington, D.C.: U.S. Government Printing Office, 1977. DHEW Publication No. (FDA)77-3041.
  • U.S. Department of Health and Human Services. Public Health Service. Food and Drug Administration. Guidelines for the Format and Content of the Clinical and Statistical Sections of New Drug Applications. Washington, D.C.: U.S. Government Printing Office, 1988.
  • U.S. Department of Health and Human Services. Public Health Service. Food and Drug Administration. General Considerations for the Clinical Evaluation of Drugs. Washington, D.C.: U.S. Government Printing Office, 1977.
  • U.S. Department of Health and Human Services. Public Health Service. National Institutes of Health. “Policy Concerning Inclusion of Women and Minorities in Study Populations. NIH Guide for Grants and Contracts 20 (No. 32, August 23, 1991): 1-3. The policy also appears in the application packet for Public Health Service Grants, form PHS 398, pp. 21-22, and in NIH Requests for Proposals (RFPs).
  • U.S. General Accounting Office. Women’s Health: FDA Needs to Ensure More Study of Gender Differences in Prescription Drug Testing. Washington, D.C.: U.S. Government Printing Office, October 1992. GAO/HRD-93-17.
  • van Lier, Donna J., and Roberts, Joyce E. “Promoting Informed Consent of Women in Labor.” Journal of Obstetric, Gynecologic and Neonatal Nursing 15 (No. 5, September-October 1986): 419-422.

C. Children and Minors

  • Ackerman, Terrence F. “Protectionism and the New Research Imperative in Pediatric AIDS.” IRB 12 (No. 5, September/October 1990):1-5.
  • Annas, George J. “Baby Fae: The ‘Anything Goes’ School of Human Experimentation.” Hastings Center Report 15 (No. 1, February 1985): 15-17.
  • Bjune, Gunnar, and Arnesen, qyvind. “Problems Related to Informed Consent from Young Teenagers Participating in Efficacy Testing of a New Vaccine.” IRB 14 (No. 5, September/October 1992): 6-9.
  • Carter, Michele; McCarthy, Charles R.; and Wichman, Alison. “Regulating AIDS Research on Infants and Children: The Moral Task of Institutional Review Boards.” Bridges 2 (No. ½, Spring/Summer 1990): 63-73.
  • Gaylin, Willard. “The Competence of Children C No Longer All or None.” Hastings Center Report 12 (No. 2, April 1982): 33-38.
  • Gaylin, Willard, and Macklin, Ruth, eds. Who Speaks for the Child: The Problems of Proxy Consent. New York and London: Plenum Press, 1982.
  • Holder, Angela R. “Constraints on Experimentation: Protecting Children to Death.” Yale Law and Policy Review 6 (No. 1, 1988): 137-156.
  • Holder, Angela Roddey. “The Minor as Research Subject or Transplant Donor.” In Legal Issues in Pediatrics and Adolescent Medicine, 2d ed., by Angela Roddey Holder, pp. 146-178. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1985.
  • Jonsen, Albert. “Research Involving Children: The Recommendations of the National Commission for the Protection of Human Subjects of Biomedical and Behavioral Research.” Pediatrics 62 (No. 2, August 1978): 131-136.
  • Kopelman, Loretta M. “When is the Risk Minimal Enough for Children to be Research Subjects?” In Children and Health Care: Moral and Social Issues, edited by Loretta M. Kopelman, and John C. Moskop, pp. 89-99. Boston: Kluwer Academic, 1989.
  • Kopelman, Loretta, and Moskop, John C., eds. Children and Health Care: Moral and Social Issues. Boston: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1989.
  • Koren, Gideon, and Pastuszak, Anne. “Medical Research in Infants and Children in the Eighties: Analysis of Rejected Protocols.” Pediatric Research 27 (No. 5, May 1990): 432-435.
  • Langer, Dennis H. “Medical Research Involving Children: Some Legal and Ethical Issues.” Baylor Law Review 36 (No. 1, Winter 1984): 1-120.
  • Levine, Carol. “Children in HIV/AIDS Clinical Trials: Still Vulnerable after All These Years.” Law, Medicine and Health Care 19 (No. 3-4, Fall/Winter 1991): 231-37.
  • Levine, Robert J. “Children as Research Subjects.” In Children and Health Care: Moral and Social Issues, edited by Loretta M. Kopelman and John C. Moskop, pp. 73-87. Boston: Kluwer Academic, 1989.
  • Levine, Robert J. Ethics and Regulation of Clinical Research. 2d ed. Baltimore: Urban and Schwarzenberg, 1986. See Chapter 10, “Children.”
  • Martin, Judith M., and Sacks, Henry S. “Do HIV-Infected Children in Foster Care Have Access to Clinical Trials of New Treatments?” AIDS and Public Policy Journal 5 (No. 1, Winter 1990): 3-8.
  • Mason, John Kenyon. “Consent to Treatment and Research in Children.” In Medico-Legal Aspects of Reproduction and Parenthood, edited by John Kenyon Mason, pp. 280-296. Brookfield, VT: Gower, 1990.
  • McClosky, Sandra Graham. “Research and Treatment: Ethical Distinctions Related to the Care of Children.” Journal of Pediatric Nursing 2 (No. 1, February 1987): 23-29.
  • Mishkin, Barbara. “The Report and Recommendations of the National Commission for the Protection of Human Subjects: Research Involving Children.” In Advances in Law and Child Development: A Research Annual, Vol. 1, edited by Robert L. Sprague, pp. 63-96. Greenwich, Conn: JAI Press, Inc., 1982.
  • Prentice, Ernest D. et al. “Can Children be Enrolled in a Placebo-Controlled Randomized Clinical Trial of Synthetic Growth Hormone?” IRB 11 (No. 1, January/February 1989): 6-10.
  • Sheldon, Mark, and Sheldon, Bonita Bergman. “Adolescents and Informed Consent.” In Medical Ethics: A Guide for Health Professionals, edited by John F. Monagle and David C. Thomasma. Rockville, MD: Aspen Publishers, 1988.
  • Silverman, William A. “SSPR Mini-Symposium: Methodologic Controversies in Clinical Research: Consent for Experimentation Involving Neonates.” American Journal of the Medical Sciences 296 (No. 5, November 1988): 354-359.
  • Thompson, Ross A. “Vulnerability in Research: A Developmental Perspective on Research Risk.” Child Development 61 (No. 1, February 1990): 1-16.
  • U.S. Department of Health and Human Services. Public Health Service. Food and Drug Administration. Guidelines for the Clinical Evaluation of Psychoactive Drugs in Infants and Children. Washington, D.C.: U.S. Government Printing Office, 1979. HEW Publication No. (FDA) 79-3055.
  • U.S. Department of Health and Human Services. Public Health Service. Food and Drug Administration. General Considerations for the Clinical Evaluation of Drugs in Infants and Children. Washington, D.C.: U.S. Government Printing Office, 1977. HEW Publication No. (FDA) 77-3041.
  • U.S. Department of Health and Human Services. Public Health Service. National Institutes of Health. Final Report, Secretary’s Work Group on Pediatric HIV Infection and Diseases. Washington, D.C.: Government Printing Office, November 18, 1988. NIH Publication No. 89-3063.
  • U.S. National Commission for the Protection of Human Subjects. Report and Recommendations: Research Involving Children. Washington, D.C.: U.S. Government Printing Office, 1977. DHEW Publication No. (OS) 77-005. Reprinted in Federal Register 43 (January 13, 1978): 2084.
  • U.S. National Commission for the Protection of Human Subjects. Appendix to Report and Recommendations: Research Involving Children. Washington, D.C.: U.S. Government Printing Office, 1977. DHEW Publication No. (OS) 77-0005.
  • Veatch, Robert M. The Patient as Partner: A Theory of Human-Experimentation Ethics. Bloomington and Indianapolis, IN: Indiana University Press, 1987. See Chapter 15, “Contraception Research on Teenagers: Beyond Consent to Treatment.”
  • Yaffe, Sumner J. “Problems of Drug Testing in Children in the United States.” Pediatric Pharmacology 3 (No. ¾, 1983): 339-348.

D. Cognitively Impaired Persons

  • American College of Physicians. “Cognitively Impaired Subjects.” Annals of Internal Medicine 111 (No. 10, November 15, 1989): 843-848.
  • Annas, George J., and Glantz, L. H. “Rules for Research in Nursing Homes.” New England Journal of Medicine 315 (No. 18, October 30, 1986): 1157-1158.
  • Appelbaum, Paul S., and Roth, Loren H. “Competency to Consent for Research.” Archives of General Psychiatry 39 (No. 8, August 1982): 951-958.
  • Baudouin, Jean-Louis. “Biomedical Experimentation on the Mentally Handicapped: Ethical and Legal Dilemmas.” Medicine and Law 9 (No. 4, 1990): 1052-1061.
  • Benson, Paul R. et al. “Information Disclosure, Subject Understanding, and Informed Consent in Psychiatric Research.” Law and Human Behavior 12 (No. 4, December 1988): 455-475.
  • Davis, Anne J., and Mahon, Kathleen A. “Research with the Mentally Retarded and Mentally Ill: Rights and Duties versus Compelling State Interest.” Journal of Advanced Nursing 9 (No. 1, January 1984): 15-21.
  • Dubler, Nancy Neveloff. “Legal Issues in Research on Institutionalized Demented Patients.” In Alzheimer’s Dementia: Dilemmas in Clinical Research, edited by Vijaya L. Melnick, and Nancy N. Dubler, pp. 149-173. Clifton, NJ: Humana Press, 1985.
  • Dyer, Allen R. “Assessment of Competence to Give Informed Consent.” In Alzheimer’s Dementia: Dilemmas in Clinical Research, edited by Vijaya L. Melnick, and Nancy N. Dubler, pp. 227-237. Clifton, NJ: Humana Press, 1985.
  • Euretig, J.G. “Legal and Ethical Aspects of Deliberate G-Induced Loss of Consciousness Experiments.” Aviation, Space, and Environmental Medicine 62 (No. 7, July 1991): 628-631.
  • Fletcher, John C.; Dommel, F. William, Jr.; and Cowell, Daniel D. “Consent to Research with Impaired Human Subjects: A Trial Policy for the Intramural Programs of the National Institutes of Health.” IRB 7 (No. 6, November/December 1985): 1-6.
  • Hickman, J.R., Jr. “Panel Summary: From Zen Riddle to the Razor’s Edge.” Aviation, Space, and Environmental Medicine 62 (No. 7, July 1991): 632-637.
  • Lebacqz, Karen. “Beyond Respect for Persons and Beneficence: Justice in Research.” IRB 2 (No. 7, August/September 1980): 1-4.
  • Levenson, James L., and Hamric, Ann B. “Ethical Dilemmas in the Treatment of Patients Following Traumatic Brain Injury.” Psychiatric Medicine 7 (No. 1, 1989): 59-71. See especially pp. 68-70.
  • Meisel, Alan. “Assuring Adequate Consent: Special Considerations in Patients of Uncertain Competence.” In Alzheimer’s Dementia: Dilemmas in Clinical Research, edited by Vijaya L. Melnick and Nancy N. Dubler, pp. 205-226. Clifton, NJ: Humana Press, 1985.
  • Meisel, Alan, and Kabnick, Lisa D. “Informed Consent to Medical Treatment: An Analysis of Recent Legislation.” University of Pittsburgh Law Review 41 (Spring 1980): 407-564.
  • Melnick, Vijaya L., and Dubler, Nancy N., eds. Alzheimer’s Dementia: Dilemmas in Clinical Research. Clifton, NJ: Humana Press, 1985.
  • Miller, Bruce. “Autonomy and Proxy Consent.” In Alzheimer’s Dementia: Dilemmas in Clinical Research, edited by Vijaya L. Melnick and Nancy N. Dubler, pp. 239-263. Clifton, NJ: Humana Press, 1985.
  • National Conference of Commissioners on Uniform State Laws. Model Health Care Consent Act of the National Conference of Commissioners on Uniform State Laws. Chicago, IL: National Conference of Commissioners on Uniform State Laws, 1982.
  • Ratzan, Richard M. “Technical Aspects of Obtaining Informed Consent from Persons with Senile Dementia of the Alzheimer’s Type.” In Alzheimer’s Dementia: Dilemmas in Clinical Research, edited by Vijaya L. Melnick and Nancy N. Dubler, pp. 123-139. Clifton, NJ: Humana Press, 1985.
  • Reatig, Natalie, ed. Competency and Informed Consent: Papers and Other Materials Developed for the Workshop “Empirical Research on Informed Consent with Subjects of Uncertain Competence, Alcohol, Drug Abuse, and Mental Health Administration.” [Department of Health and Human Services, January 12-13, 1981.] Rockville, MD: National Institute of Mental Health, 1981.
  • Roth, Loren et al. “Competency to Decide About Treatment or Research.” International Journal of Law and Psychology 5 (No. 1, 1982): 29-50.
  • Stanley, Barbara. “Ethical Considerations in Biological Research on Suicide.” In Psychobiology of Suicidal Behavior, edited by J. Mann and M. Stanley, pp. 42-46. New York: New York Academy of Sciences, 1986.
  • Stanley, Barbara, and Stanley, Michael. “Testing Competency in Psychiatric Patients.” IRB 4 (No. 8, October 1982): 1-6.
  • Tibbles, Lance. “Derived Consent, Proxy Consent: Legal Issues.” In Alzheimer’s Dementia: Dilemmas in Clinical Research, edited by Vijaya L. Melnick and Nancy N. Dubler, pp. 265-294. Clifton, NJ: Humana Press, 1985.
  • U.S. Department of Health and Human Services. Public Health Service. Food and Drug Administration. Guidelines for the Clinical Evaluation of Psychoactive Drugs in Infants and Children. Washington, D.C.: U.S. Government Printing Office, 1979. HEW Publication No. (FDA) 79-3055.
  • U.S. Department of Health and Human Services. Public Health Service. Food and Drug Administration. Guidelines for the Clinical Evaluation of Hypnotic Drugs. Washington, D.C.: U.S. Government Printing Office, 1978. HEW Publication No. (FDA) 78-3051.
  • U.S. Department of Health and Human Services. Public Health Service. Food and Drug Administration. Guidelines for the Clinical Evaluation of Antidepressant Drugs. Washington, D.C.: U.S. Government Printing Office, 1977. HEW Publication No. (FDA) 77-3042.
  • U.S. Department of Health and Human Services. Public Health Service. Food and Drug Administration. Guidelines for the Clinical Evaluation of Antianxiety Drugs. Washington, D.C.: U.S. Government Printing Office, 1977. HEW Publication No. (FDA) 77-3043.
  • U.S. Department of Health, Education and Welfare. “Determination of Secretary Regarding Recommendations on Psychosurgery of the National Commission for the Protection of Human Subjects of Biomedical and Behavioral Research.” Federal Register 43 (November 15, 1978): 54242.
  • U.S. Department of Health and Human Services. Public Health Service. National Institute on Alcohol Abuse and Alcoholism. “Recommended Council Guidelines on Ethyl Alcohol Administration in Human Experimentation.” Revised June 1989.
  • U.S. National Commission for the Protection of Human Subjects of Biomedical and Behavioral Research. Report and Recommendations: Research Involving Those Institutionalized as Mentally Infirm. Washington, D.C.: U.S. Government Printing Office, 1978. HEW Publication No. (OS) 78-0006. Reprinted in Federal Register 43 (March 17, 1978): 11328.
  • U.S. National Commission for the Protection of Human Subjects of Biomedical and Behavioral Research. Report and Recommendations: Psychosurgery. Washington, D.C.: U.S. Government Printing Office, 1977. HEW Publication No. (OS) 77-001. Reprinted in Federal Register 42 (May 23, 1977): 26318.

E. Prisoners

  • Annas, George; Glantz, Leonard; and Katz, Barbara. Informed Consent to Experimentation: The Subject’s Dilemma. Cambridge, MA: Ballinger Publishing Co., 1977.
  • Bach-y-Rita. “The Prisoner as an Experimental Subject.” Journal of the American Medical Association 229 (1974): 45.
  • Dubler, Nancy N., and Levine, Robert J. “The Burdens of Research in Prisons.” [Letter and response.] IRB 4 (No. 9, November 1982): 9-11.
  • Dubler, Nancy N., and Sidel, Victor W. “On Research on HIV Infection in Correctional Institutions.” Milbank Quarterly 67 (No. 2, 1989): 171-207.
  • Fry, Sigrid. “Experimentation on Prisoners’ Remains.” American Criminal Law Review 24 (No. 1, Summer 1986): 166-191.
  • Jonsen, Albert et al. “Biomedical Experimentation on Prisoners: Review of Practices and Problems and a Proposal of a New Regulatory Approach.” Ethics in Science and Medicine 4 (No. ½, 1977): 1-28.
  • Lebacqz, Karen. “Beyond Respect for Persons and Beneficence: Justice in Research.” IRB 2 (No. 7, August/September 1980): 1-4.
  • Levine, Robert J. Ethics and Regulation of Clinical Research. 2d ed. Baltimore: Urban and Schwarzenberg, 1986. See Chapter 12, “Prisoners.”
  • Levine, Robert J. “Research on Prisoners: Why Not?” IRB 4 (No. 5, May 1982): 6. See also letter by N. Dubler and response by R. Levine in IRB 4 (No. 9, November 1982): 9-11.
  • Novick, Alvin. “Clinical Trials with Vulnerable or Disrespected Subjects.” AIDS and Public Policy Journal 4 (No. 2, 1989): 125-130.
  • Pattullo, E.L. “Case Study: Transforming a Personal Inquiry into a Research Project.” IRB 3 (No. 4, April 1981): 5-6.
  • U.S. National Commission for the Protection of Human Subjects of Biomedical and Behavioral Research. Report and Recommendations: Research Involving Prisoners. Washington, D.C.: U.S. Government Printing Office, 1976. DHEW Publication No. (OS) 76-131. Reprinted in Federal Register 42 (January 14, 1977): 3076.
  • U.S. National Commission for the Protection of Human Subjects of Biomedical and Behavioral Research. Appendix to Report and Recommendations: Research Involving Prisoners. Washington, D.C.: U.S. Government Printing Office, 1976. DHEW Publication No. (OS) 76-132.
  • U.S. President’s Commission for the Study of Ethical Problems in Medicine and Biomedical and Behavioral Research. Biennial Report on Protecting Human Subjects. Washington, D.C.: U.S. Government Printing Office, 1981. See Appendix B.
  • Veatch, Robert M. The Patient as Partner: A Theory of Human-Experimentation Ethics. Bloomington and Indianapolis, IN: Indiana University Press, 1987. See especially pp. 60-61.
  • Winkleman, Laurie. “Drug Testing in Prisons.” In Troubling Problems in Medical Ethics. Proceedings of the 1980 and 1981 Conferences on Ethics, Humanism, and Medicine at the University of Michigan, Ann Arbor. Edited by Marc D. Basson, Rachel E. Lipson, and Doreen L. Ganos. New York: A.R. Liss, 1981.

F. Traumatized and Comatose Patients

  • Abramson, Norman S., and Safar, Peter. “Deferred Consent: Use in Cinical Resuscitation Research.” Annals of Emergency Medicine 19 (No. 7, July 1990): 781-784.
  • Abramson, Norman S.; Meisel, Alan; and Safar, Peter. “Deferred Consent: A New Approach for Resuscitation Research on Comatose Patients.” Journal of the American Medical Association 255 (No. 18, May 9, 1986): 2466-2471.
  • Abramson, Norman S.; Meisel, Alan; and Safar, Peter. “Informed Consent in Resuscitation Research.” Journal of the American Medical Association 246 (No. 24, December 18, 1981): 2828-2830.
  • Fost, Norman, and Robertson, John. “Deferring Consent with Incompetent Patients in an Intensive Care Unit.” IRB 2 (No. 7, August/September 1980): 5-6. Commentary by Tom Beauchamp, p. 6.
  • Frank, Stuart, and Agich, George J. “Nontherapeutic Research on Subjects Unable to Grant Consent.” Clinical Research 33 (No. 4, October 1985): 459-64.
  • Grim, Pamela S. et al. “Informal Consent in Emergency Research: Prehospital Thrombolytic Therapy for Acute Myocardial Infarction.” Journal of the American Medical Association 262 (No. 2, July 14, 1989): 252-255. Letter and comments in Journal of the American Medical Association 262 (No. 22, December 8, 1989): 3129.
  • Meisel, Alan, and Kabnick, Lisa D. “Informed Consent to Medical Treatment: An Analysis of Recent Legislation.” University of Pittsburgh Law Review 41 (Spring 1980): 407-564.
  • National Conference of Commissioners on Uniform State Laws. Model Health Care Consent Act. In Uniform Laws Annotated Vol. 9, Pt. I. St. Paul, MN: West Publishing Co. (1992 Supp.).
  • Spivey, William H. “Informed Consent for Clinical Research in the Emergency Department.” Annals of Emergency Medicine 18 (No. 7, July 1989): 766-771.
  • U.S. Department of Health and Human Services. Public Health Service. Food and Drug Administration. “Emergency Use of an Investigational Drug.” FDA IRB Information Sheets, February, 1989.

Previously titled “Emergency Use of a Test Article.”

  • U.S. Department of Health and Human Services. Public Health Service. National Institutes of Health. “Emergency Medical Care” [Dear Colleague Letter.] OPRR Reports, May 15, 1991.
  • Young, Ernle W. D. “When Critical Illness Interferes with Informed Consent.” Progress in Clinical and Biological Research 299 (1989): 235-239.

G. Terminally Ill Patients

  • American Society of Law and Medicine. Ethical and Legal Aspects of Treatment for Critically and Terminally Ill Patients. [Continuing Series.] Boston, MA: American Society of Law and Medicine.
  • Annas, George J. “Baby Fae: The ‘Anything Goes’ School of Human Experimentation.” Hastings Center Report 15 (No. 1, February 1985): 15-17.
  • Capron, Alexander M. “Informed Consent in Catastrophic Disease Research and Treatment.” University of Pennsylvania Law Review 123 (No. 2, December 1974): 340-438.
  • Corless, Inge B. “Physicians and Nurses: Roles and Responsibilities in Caring for the Critically Ill Patient.” Law, Medicine and Health Care 10 (No. 2, April 1982): 72-76.
  • Deutch, Erwin. The Dying Human. Tel Aviv: Turtledove Publishing, 1979.
  • Schoene-Sifert, Bettina, and Childress, James F. “How Much Should the Cancer Patient Know and Decide?” CA - A Cancer Journal for Clinicians 36 (No. 2, March/April 1986): 85-94.
  • Taub, Sheila. “Cancer and the Law of Informed Consent.” Law, Medicine and Health Care 10 (No. 2, April 1982): 61-66, 90.
  • U.S. Department of Health and Human Services. Public Health Service. Task Force on NCI-FDA Investigational New Drugs. Report on Anticancer Drugs: The National Cancer Institute’s Development and the Food and Drug Administration’s Regulation, Vol. 2. Washington, D.C.: Department of Health and Human Services, Public Health Service, 1982. See especially Chapter X, “Therapeutic Intent” and Chapter XI, “Protection of Human Subjects C Informed Consent and IRBs.”
  • Young, Ernle W. D. “When Critical Illness Interferes with Informed Consent.” Progress in Clinical and Biological Research 299 (1989): 235-239.

H. Elderly/Aged Persons

  • Annas, George J., and Glantz, Leonard H. “Rules for Research in Nursing Homes.” New England Journal of Medicine 315 (No. 18, October 30, 1986): 1157-1158.
  • Cassel, Christine K. “Informed Consent for Research in Geriatrics: History and Concepts.” Journal of the American Geriatrics Society 35 (No. 6, June 1987): 542-544.
  • Cassel, Christine K. Cassel. “Ethical Issues in Research in Geriatrics.” Generations: The Journal of the Western Gerontological Society 10 (No. 2, Winter 1985): 45-48.
  • Dubler, Nancy Neveloff. “Legal Judgments and Informed Consent in Geriatric Research.” Journal of the American Geriatrics Society 35 (No. 6, June 1987): 545-549.
  • Hoffman, Pamela B., and Libow, Leslie S. “The Need for Alternatives to Informed Consent by Older Patients: Psychological and Physical Aspects of the Institutionalized Elderly.” In Alzheimer’s Dementia: Dilemmas in Clinical Research, edited by Vijaya L. Melnick and Nancy N. Dubler, pp. 141-148. Clifton, NJ: Humana Press, 1985.
  • Jameton, Andrew. “An Alternative Approach to Informed Consent in Research with Vulnerable Patients.” In Alzheimer’s Dementia: Dilemmas in Clinical Research, edited by Vijaya L. Melnick and Nancy N. Dubler, pp. 109-122. Clifton, NJ: Humana Press, 1985.
  • Lane, L.W.; Cassel, C.K.; and Bennett, W. “Ethical Aspects of Research Involving Elderly Subjects: Are We Doing More Than We Say?” Journal of Clinical Ethics 1 (No. 4, Winter 1990): 278-285. Published erratum appears in Journal of Clinical Ethics 2 (No. 1, Spring 1991): 4.
  • Levine, Robert J. Ethics and Regulation of Clinical Research. 2d ed. Baltimore: Urban and Schwarzenberg, 1986.
  • Lipsitz, Lewis A.; Pluchino, Frances C.; and Wright, Susan B. “Biomedical Research in the Nursing Home: Methodological Issues and Subject Recruitment Results.” Journal of the American Geriatrics Society 35 (No. 7, July 1987): 629-634.
  • Ratzan, Richard M. “Communication and Informed Consent in Clinical Geriatrics.” International Journal of Aging and Human Development 23 (No. 1, 1986): 17-26.
  • Sachs, Greg A., and Cassel, Christine K. “Biomedical Research Involving Older Human Subjects.” Law, Medicine and Health Care 18 (No. 3, Fall 1990): 234-243.
  • Stanley, Barbara, ed. Geriatric Psychiatry: Clinical, Ethical and Legal Issues. Washington: American Psychiatric Press, 1985.
  • Taub, Harvey A. et al. “Informed Consent for Research: Effects of Readability, Patient Age, and Education.” Journal of the American Geriatrics Society 34 (No. 8, August 1986): 601-606.
  • U.S. National Research Council. Committee on Models for Biomedical Research. Models for Biomedical Research: A New Perspective. Washington, D.C.: National Academy Press, 1985. See especially Appendix E, “Models for the Study of Diseases and Aging.”
  • Warren, John W. et al. “Informed Consent by Proxy: An Issue in Research with Elderly Patients.” New England Journal of Medicine 315 (No. 18, October 30, 1986): 1124-1128.

I. Minorities

  • Caplan, Arthur L. “When Evil Intrudes.” The Hastings Center Report 22 (No. 6, November/December 1992): 29-32.
  • Clemmit, Marcia. “Clinical Researchers Adapting to Mandate for More Diversity in Study Populations.” The Scientist 5 (No. 18, September 16, 1991): 1.
  • Edgar, Harold. “Outside the Community.” The Hastings Center Report 22 (No. 6, November/December 1992): 32-35.
  • Jones, James H. “The Tuskegee Legacy: AIDS and the Black Community.” The Hastings Center Report 22 (No. 6, November/December 1992): 38-40.
  • King, Patricia. “The Dangers of Difference.” The Hastings Center Report 22 (No. 6, November/December 1992): 33-38.
  • Levine, Robert J. Ethics and Regulation of Clinical Research. 2d ed. Baltimore: Urban and Schwarzenberg, 1986. See Chapter 4, “Selection of Subjects.”
  • Svensson, Craig K. “Representation of American Blacks in Clinical Trials of New Drugs.” Journal of the American Medical Association 261 (No. 2, January 13, 1989): 263-265.
  • Thomas, S.B., and Quinn, S.C. “The Tuskegee Syphilis Study, 1932-1972: Implications for HIV Education and AIDS Risk Education Programs in the Black Community.” American Journal of Public Health 81 (No. 11, November 1991): 1498-1505.
  • Twenty Years After: The Legacy of the Tuskegee Syphilis Study. The Hastings Center Report 22 (No. 6, November/December 1992): 29-40. Articles by Caplan, Edgar, King, and Jones listed in this bibliography.
  • U.S. Department of Health and Human Services. Public Health Service. National Institutes of Health. “Policy Concerning Inclusion of Women and Minorities in Study Populations. NIH Guide for Grants and Contracts 20 (No. 32, August 23, 1991): 1-3. The policy also appears in the application packet for Public Health Service Grants, form PHS 398, pp. 21-22, and in NIH Requests for Proposals (RFPs).

J. Students, Employees, and Normal Volunteers

  • Altman, Lawrence K. Who Goes First? The Story of Self-Experimentation in Medicine. New York: Random House, 1987.
  • Angoff, Nancy R. “Against Special Protections for Medical Students.” IRB 7 (No. 5, September/October 1985): 9-10.
  • Burchell, Howard B. “The Investigator as Volunteer Subject.” Mayo Clinic Proceedings 57 (Supp., July 1982): 28-33.
  • Brazzell, Romulus K., and Colburn, Wayne A. “Controversy I: Patients or Healthy Volunteers for Pharmacokinetic Studies?” Journal of Clinical Pharmacology 26 (No. 4, April 1986): 242-254.
  • Christakis, Nicholas. “Do Medical Student Research Subjects Need Special Protection?” IRB 7 (No. 3, May/June 1985): 1-4.
  • Cohen, Jeffrey M. “Extra Credit for Research Subjects.” IRB 4 (No. 8, October 1982): 10-11.
  • Fazackerley, E. J.; Randall, N. P. C.; and Pleuvry, B. J. “Three Cases of Illness During a Drug Trial in Healthy Volunteers.” British Medical Journal 294 (February 28, 1987): 562-563.
  • Fleming, Michael F. et al. “Informed Consent, Deception, and the Use of Disguised Alcohol Questionnaires.” American Journal of Drug and Alcohol Abuse 15 (No. 3, 1989): 309-319.
  • Forrester, J. M. “Using Oneself as One’s Only Experimental Subject.” The Lancet 336 (No. 8718, September 29, 1990): 798-799. See also letter by J.J.E. van Everdingen and A.F. Cohen in The Lancet 336 (No. 8728, December 8, 1990):1448.
  • Gamble, H. F. “Case Study: Students, Grades and Informed Consent.” IRB 4 (No. 5, May 1982): 7-10.
  • Harry, J.D. “Research on Healthy Volunteers: A Report of the Royal College of Physicians.” British Journal of Clinical Pharmacology 23 (No. 4, April 1987): 379-381.
  • Howe, Edmund G., III; Kark, John A.; and Wright, Daniel G. “Studying Sickle Cell Trait in Healthy Army Recruits: Should the Research Be Done?” Clinical Research 31 (No. 2, April 1983): 119-125.
  • Levine, Robert J. Ethics and Regulation of Clinical Research. 2d ed. Baltimore: Urban and Schwarzenberg, 1986. See pp. 80-82 (students and employees) and p. 291 (employees).
  • Levine, Robert J. “What Kind of Subjects Can Understand This Protocol?” IRB 6 (No. 5, September/October 1984): 6-8.
  • Levine, Robert J. “Research on Prisoners: Why Not?” IRB 4 (No. 5, May 1982): 6. See also letter by Nancy Dubler and response by Robert Levine in IRB 4 (No. 9, November 1982): 9-11.
  • Macrae, Finlay A.; Mackay, Ian R.; and Fraser, J. Robert E. “Participation of Healthy Volunteers in Research Projects.” The Medical Journal of Australia 150 (No. 6, March 20, 1989): 325-28.
  • Maloney, Dennis M. Protection of Human Research Subjects: A Practical Guide to Federal Laws and Regulations. New York: Plenum Press, 1984. See Chapter 7, “Students.”
  • Meyers, K. “Drug Company Employees as Research Subjects: Programs, Problems, and Ethics.” IRB 1 (No. 8, December 1979): 5-6.
  • Nolan, K. A. “’Protecting’ Medical Students from the Risks of Research.” IRB 1 (No. 5, August/September 1989): 9.
  • Phillips, Michael, and Vasquez, Alfredo J. “Abnormal Findings in ‘Normal’ Research Volunteers.” Controlled Clinical Trials 8 (No. 4, December 1987): 338-342.
  • Royal College of Physicians Working Party. “Research on Healthy Volunteers.” Journal of the Royal College of Physicians 20 (1986): 3-17.
  • Shannon, Thomas A. “Case Study: Should Medical Students Be Research Subjects?” IRB 1 (No. 2, April 1979): 4.
  • Svensson, Craig K. “Is Blood Sampling for Determination of Antipyrine Pharmacokinetics in Healthy Volunteers Ethically Justified?” Clinical Pharmacology and Therapeutics 44 (No. 4, October 1988): 365-368.

K. International Research

  • Angell, Marcia. “Ethical Imperialism? Ethics in International Collaborative Clinical Research.” New England Journal of Medicine 319 (No. 16, October 20, 1988): 1081-1083.
  • Australia. National Health and Medical Research Council. Ethics in Medical Research: Report of the National Health and Medical Research Council Working Party on Ethics in Medical Research. Canberra: Australian Government Publishing Service, 1983.
  • Australia. National Health and Medical Research Council. Medical Research Ethics Committee. Report on Ethics in Epidemiological Research. Canberra: Australian Government Publishing Service, 1985.
  • Australia. National Health and Medical Research Council. Ethics in Medical Research Involving the Human Fetus and Human Fetal Tissue: Report of the National Health and Medical Research Council Medical Research Ethics Committee. Canberra: Australian Government Publishing Service, 1983.
  • Barry, Michelle. “Ethical Considerations of Human Investigation in Developing Countries: The AIDS Dilemma.” New England Journal of Medicine 319 (No. 16, October 20, 1988): 1085-1083.
  • Canada. Medical Research Council of Canada. Guidelines on Research Involving Human Subjects. Ottawa: Medical Research Council of Canada, 1987.
  • Christakis, Nicholas A., and Panner, Morris J. “Existing International Ethical Guidelines for Human Subjects Research: Some Open Questions.” Law, Medicine and Health Care 19 (No. 3-4, Fall-Winter 1991): 214-221.
  • Christakis, Nicholas A. “Ethical Design of an AIDS Vaccine Trial in Africa.” Hastings Center Report 18 (No. 3, June/July 1988): 31-37.
  • Cooper, J.E. “Balancing the Scales of Public Interest: Medical Research and Privacy.” Medical Journal of Australia 155 (No. 8, October 21, 1991): 556-560.
  • Council of Europe. Parliamentary Assembly. “Recommendation 1100 (1989): On the Use of Human Embryos and Foetuses in Scientific Research.” Strasbourg: The Council, 1989. Adopted by the Assembly on February 2, 1989.
  • Council for International Organizations of Medical Sciences (CIOMS). International Ethical Guidelines for Biomedical Research Involving Human Subjects. Geneva: Council for International Organizations of Medical Sciences, 1993.
  • Council for International Organizations of Medical Sciences (CIOMS). Safety Requirements for the First Use of New Drugs and Diagnostic Agents in Man: A Review of Safety Issues in Early Clinical Trials of Drugs. Geneva: Council for International Organizations of Medical Sciences, 1983.
  • Council for International Organizations of Medical Sciences (CIOMS). International Guidelines for Ethical Review of Epidemiological Studies. Geneva: Council for International Organizations of Medical Sciences, 1991. Reprinted in Law, Medicine and Health Care 19 (No. 3-4, Fall/Winter 1991): 247-58.
  • Curran, William J. “Clinical Investigations in Developing Countries: Legal and Regulatory Issues in the Promotion of Research and the Protection of Human Rights.” In The Law-Medicine Relation: A Philosophical Exploration, edited by Stuart F. Spicker, Joseph M. Healey, and H. Tristram Engelhardt, pp. 53-74. Boston: D. Reidel, 1981.
  • Declaration of Helsinki. See World Medical Association (1989).
  • European Parliament. Committee on Legal Affairs and Citizens’ Rights. “Ethical and Legal Problems of Genetic Engineering, and Human Artificial Insemination.” Resolution of March 16, 1989. Official Journal of the European Communities 17.4.89, pp. C 96/165-170. Reprinted (slightly abridged) in Bulletin of Medical Ethics 57 (April 1990): 8-10.
  • France. Ministry of Social Affairs and Mutual Assistance. Minister Delegate for Health. Protection of Persons Undergoing Biomedical Research: I. Acts of Parliament; II. Delegated Legislation. [English language translation (unofficial) of relevant laws dated December 1988 through January 1991.] Paris: The Ministry of Social Affairs and Mutual Assistance, 1991.
  • France. ComitJ consultatif national d’Jthique pour les sciences de la vie et de la santJ. Ethique et recherche biomJdicale: Rapport 1988. Paris: La Documentation francaise, 1989.
  • France. Direction de la Documentation francaise. Notes et Jtudes documentaires, No. 4855 (1988, No. 5): Sciences de la vie: De l’Jthique au droit.
  • German Medical Association. Federal Medical Board. Scientific Advisory Board. “Guidelines Concerning Research on Early Human Embryos.” [English translation.] World Medical Journal 33 (Nos. 2/3, 1986): 29-33.
  • Great Britain. Department of Health and Social Security. Committee of Inquiry into Human Fertilisation and Embryology. Mary Warnock, Chair. A Question of Life: The Warnock Report on Human Fertilisation and Embryology. New York: Basil Blackwell, 1985. Text of 1984 Report, with added introduction and conclusion by Mary Warnock.
  • Great Britain. Institute of Medical Ethics. “Gene Therapy.” Briefings in Medical Ethics, No. 7, December 1990.
  • Great Britain. Medical Research Council. The Ethical Conduct of AIDS Vaccine Trials: Report of the Working Party on Ethical Aspects of AIDS Vaccine Trials. MRC Ethics Series. London: Medical Research Council, 1991.
  • Great Britain. Medical Research Council. Working Party on Research on Children. The Ethical Conduct of Research On Children. MRC Ethics Series. London: Medical Research Council, 1991.
  • Great Britain. Medical Research Council. “Responsibility in the Use of Personal Medical Information for Research: Principles and Guide to Practice.” British Medical Journal 290 (April 13, 1985): 1120-1124.
  • Haynes, W.G., and Webb, D.J. “Ethics of Volunteer Research: The Role of the New EC Guidelines.” British Journal of Clinical Pharmacology 32 (No. 6, December 1991): 671-676.
  • Helsinki Declaration. See World Medical Association (1989).
  • IJsselmuiden, Carel B., and Faden, Ruth. “Research and Informed Consent in Africa C Another Look.” New England Journal of Medicine 326 (No. 12, March 19, 1992): 830-834.
  • International Committee of Medical Journal Editors. “Statements from the International Committee of Medical Journal Editors.” Journal of the American Medical Association 265 (No. 20, May 22/29, 1991): 2697-98.
  • Law, Medicine and Health Care 19 (No. 3-4, Fall/Winter 1991). This entire issue is devoted to international human subjects research.
  • Miller, Judith. “Towards an International Ethic for Research with Human Beings.” IRB 10 (No. 6, November/December 1988): 9.
  • Nuremberg Code, The. Reprinted in Trials of War Criminals before the Nuernberg Military Tribunals under Control Council Law No. 10, Vol. 2, pp. 181-182. Washington, D.C.: U.S. Government Printing Office, 1949. Also reprinted in Ethics and Regulation of Clinical Research, 2d ed., by Robert J. Levine, pp. 425-426. Baltimore: Urban and Schwarzenberg, 1986.
  • Osborne, L.W. “Research on Human Subjects: Australian Ethics Committees Take Tentative Steps.” Journal of Medical Ethics 9 (1983): 66-68.
  • U.S. Department of Health and Human Services. Public Health Service. “U.S. Public Health Service Consultation on International Collaborative Human Immunodeficiency Virus (HIV).” Reprinted in Law, Medicine and Health Care 19 (No. 3-4, Fall/Winter 1991): 259-263.
  • West Germany. Enquete Commission. “An Extract from Prospects and Risks of Gene Technology: The Report of the Enquete Commission to the Bundestag of the Federal Republic of Germany.” Bioethics 2 (No. 3, July 1988): 254-263.
  • World Health Organization, and the Council for International Organizations of Medical Sciences. Proposed International Guidelines for Biomedical Research Involving Human Subjects: A Joint Project of the World Health Organization and the Council for International Organizations of Medical Sciences. Geneva: Council for International Organizations of Medical Sciences, 1982. [Under revision.]
  • World Medical Association. “Declaration of Helsinki.” As amended by the 41st World Medical Assembly, Hong Kong, September 1989. Reprinted in Law, Medicine and Health Care 19 (No. 3-4, Fall/Winter 1991): 264-265.

 

Return to Top of Page

________________________
Chapter VI: Special Classes of Subjects