[NIFL-ASSESSMENT:561] postpositivism

From: George E. Demetrion (socrates555@juno.com)
Date: Mon May 17 2004 - 20:39:08 EDT


Return-Path: <nifl-assessment@literacy.nifl.gov>
Received: from literacy (localhost [127.0.0.1]) by literacy.nifl.gov (8.10.2/8.10.2) with SMTP id i4I0d8m22894; Mon, 17 May 2004 20:39:08 -0400 (EDT)
Date: Mon, 17 May 2004 20:39:08 -0400 (EDT)
Message-Id: <20040517.203710.6398.0.socrates555@juno.com>
Errors-To: listowner@literacy.nifl.gov
Reply-To: nifl-assessment@literacy.nifl.gov
Originator: nifl-assessment@literacy.nifl.gov
Sender: nifl-assessment@literacy.nifl.gov
Precedence: bulk
From: "George E. Demetrion" <socrates555@juno.com>
To: Multiple recipients of list <nifl-assessment@literacy.nifl.gov>
Subject: [NIFL-ASSESSMENT:561] postpositivism
X-Listprocessor-Version: 6.0c -- ListProcessor by Anastasios Kotsikonas
X-Mailer: Juno 1.49
Status: O
Content-Length: 5936
Lines: 100

Perhaps the following might add a little more to our discussion of
postpositivism, which I am suggesting as a mediating approach to social
science research that takes into account both the ideal of exacting
analysis and maximum precision consistent with the topic at hand and
supportive data, and the complexity of the social and cultural dimensions
of such an applied field as education.

The following is a draft version of the introduction to an essay I am
proposing to write.  Whether, in the final analysis I can bring out
within a single essay the three strands of postpositivist research that I
suggest in the last paragraph remains to be seen, as I may ultimately
need to choose just one of the three for special focus.  Be that as it
may, and I believe the piece will be stronger if I can handle all three,
I am suggesting there is much to consider in the development of a
broad-based postpositivist temper that might at least modulate some of
the culture wars that characterize current discussions in adult literacy
theory and research.

Please feel free to reach me either at socrates555@juno.com or
gdemetrion@msn.com if you would prefer to comment off-line.

George Demetrion
_______________________________________________________________


The Mediating Vision of Postpositivist Science:  Three Perspectives
May `17, 2004, Draft Version

 The quest for a scientific grounding for social science research has
been a pervasive theme of 20th century scholarship.  While the search for
an exacting methodology has marked the century's efforts in the
positivist mode, criticism of this position has also been perennial.  The
problem of reductionism is the underlying concern in the challenge to
claims for any foundational basis of scientific analysis based on
inductionist theories of verification through objective observation of
given empirical data, or a priori rational principles of logic.  Critics
have noted that perception is theory-laden from inception and that both
the selection of and even definition of what counts as data is a
construct that cannot be accepted simply as given.  Additional concerns
include the problem of the underdetermination of theory by evidence that
undercuts high levels of generality allegedly discerned through
positivistic methodologies, as well as challenges to claims that analysis
can be simply broken down into component parts given the ubiquity of
situational contexts in which data is embedded, defined, and constructed
through and within.  Critics also point to the centrality of the social
dimension of social science research in which "variables" complexly
interact, making problematic the sharp separation of individual factors
of causation, which is a central objective of the positivistic quest for
precision (Phillips and Burbules, 2000, pp. 14-25).

 Notwithstanding the sophistication of the various anti-positivist
critiques, given the allure of precision as a siren call of those seeking
an exacting social science of human behavior, positivism in its several
variants has continued to maintain a prominent position in social science
research.  Still, the criticism persists that the "human factor" cannot
be calibrated into some precise equation, even as the counter pulls have
sometimes led to a relativism in which science itself is viewed as simply
another "metannarative."

 In the current era, a mediating school of thought has emerged with
postpositivism, defined in the scholarly literature in varying ways, from
that of an elaborated and up-to date form of positivism, which might be
more accurately referred to as neopositivism (Mertens, 1998), to a sharp
critique of scientific rationality itself characterized through the
pejorative term "scientism" (Hawkesworth, 1988).  Fischer (1998) provides
one mediated picture, linking postpositivism with a coherent theory of
truth and the realm of practical deliberation in the "anticipat[ion] and
draw[ing] out of the multiple interpretations that bear on the
explanation of social and political propositions".  In this he gravitates
toward the cultural axis of the postpositivist research tradition even in
his quest for maximum rigor.   

Phillips and Burbules (2000) provide a more rigorous definition in
linking postpositivsm more to the scientific pole of critical analysis. 
Drawing substantially on Dewey and Popper, Phillips and Burbules (2000)
embrace the concept of truth as a "regulative ideal."  For them,  the
quest for "reliable answers" (p. 2), what Dewey refers to as "warranted
assertions," honed through "rigorous inquiry" (p. 3), and capable of
standing up to the test of falsification, is both a feasible project for
the human sciences and essential if such research is to lead to the
progressive resolution of complex social problems.  As the authors point
out, such competent inquiries" (Dewey, 1938/1991, p. 16) require both
exacting rigor and an adequate accounting of the complexity of the
subject matter at hand.

 This paper seeks to extend the work of Fischer and Phillips and Burbules
through an exploration of three philosophical chords of 20th century
philosophy congruent with the postpositivist temper.  Specifically, I
draw on pragmatic functionalism via the experientially-premised
epistemology of John Dewey, a correspondence theory of truth via Karl
Popper's anti-positivist critical realism, and a coherence ( "optimal
systematic fit-- with the data,"  p.181) theory of truth, articulated by
contemporary philosopher Nicholas Rescher (2001).  Through this
tri-partite analysis several approaches and related issues to the
postpositivist quest for scientific rigor will be explored, as all three
authors reject both positivism and a more relativistic "interpretive"
theory of social science that averts the problem of probing into truth,
at the least as a regulative ideal.   Tensions between the scientific and
cultural poles of postpositivist philosophy are also examined.



This archive was generated by hypermail 2b30 : Thu Dec 23 2004 - 09:46:16 EST